Bryan Caplan's Blog, page 153

March 3, 2014

The Happiness of the Richest, by Bryan Caplan

Over lunch, Justin Wolfers mentioned a hard-to-believe fact: In a data set with an unusually high maximum income category, 100% of the richest people were "very happy."  I decided to track down the data.  Despite my incredulity, Justin's description was literally correct.  From a 2007 U.S. Gallup poll:

richest.jpg

Yep, 100% of the respondents with family income over half a million a year were indeed very happy.  Of course, there were only 8 such respondents.  And in the same survey, happiness was virtually flat from $30k to $150k - roughly the 20th through 90th percentiles.  Extreme Epiricureanism is both demonstrably false and approximately true.

P.S. David's thoughts about the ideological compatibility of happiness research and free-market economics make me realize I should have been clearer.  Two points:

1. David is correct to observe that diminishing marginal utility of income/wealth is entirely compatible with a suitably internationalist free-market economics.  If a dollar means more to a poor man than a rich man, using government to help relatively poor First Worlders at the expense of absolutely poor Third Worlders is morally perverse.

2. Still, the small effect of income/wealth on happiness throughout the income distribution remains ideologically inconvenient for free-market economists.  A free-market economy is a fantastic tool for making people rich, but making people rich is a mediocre tool for making people happy. 

(19 COMMENTS)
 •  0 comments  •  flag
Share on Twitter
Published on March 03, 2014 21:01

March 1, 2014

Ukrainian Prediction Challenge, by Bryan Caplan

To repeat myself:
The long-run benefits of war are highly uncertain.  Some wars -
most obviously the Napoleonic Wars and World War II - at least arguably
deserve credit for decades of subsequent peace.  But many other wars -
like the French Revolution and World War I - just sowed the seeds for
new and greater horrors.  You could say, "Fine, let's only fight wars
with big long-run benefits."  In practice, however, it's very difficult
to predict a war's long-run consequences.  One of the great lessons of Tetlock's Expert Political Judgment is that foreign policy experts are much more certain of their predictions than they have any right to be.
Challenge: In the comments, go on the record and predict what will actually come of the emerging Ukrainian-Russian conflict.  Only unconditional, falsifiable predictions count.  No claims like: "Unless the EU acts..." "If Russia comes to its senses..." or "This will be a very different world."  Make specific claims about what will actually happen by a specific date.

In a year I'll revisit your comments and rank their accuracy with the benefit of hindsight.

(31 COMMENTS)
 •  0 comments  •  flag
Share on Twitter
Published on March 01, 2014 21:06

What Say You? The Intuitive Case Against the Minimum Wage, by Bryan Caplan

Don Boudreaux asks minimum wage supporters to answer two questions they should have asked themselves long ago.

Question #1:
Name some other goods or services for which a government-mandated
price hike of 25 percent will not cause fewer units of those goods and
services to be purchased.

Beer?  Broccoli?  Bulldozers?  Coffee?  Haircuts?  Natural gas?
 Automobiles?  Housing?  Preventive health-care?  Lawn-care service?
 Tickets to the movies?  Smart phones?  Subscriptions to the New York Times?
 Books by Paul Krugman?  Professors of sociology?  Assistant professors
of economics?  Any of these products work for you?  If none of these
work, surely you can name at least one other for which a
25-percent price hike will not cause fewer units of that product to be
purchased.  Or does low-skilled labor just happen to be the one good or
service in the entire world for which a government-mandated 25-percent
rise in the price that its buyers must pay for it will not diminish
buyers' willingness to buy it?

Seriously, name just one other good or service for which you believe
that a government-mandated price-hike of  25 percent will not reduce the
quantity demanded of that good or service.

Question 2:

[B]ecause if Mr. Obama's full proposal is enacted the national minimum
wage will also from here on in be indexed to inflation, here's another
challenge to anyone who dismisses as unscientific or ideological the
standard economic argument against the minimum wage: name one other good
or service whose real price, according to economic theory, should never
fall relative to the prices of other goods or services?

The least-bad answers to Boudreaux's Question #1 that occur to me probably salt and soap.  As Oskar Lange asked in 1937: "[W]ould a decline of the price of soap to zero induce them [the "well-to-do"] to be so much more liberal in its use?"  By the standard of 1937, almost everyone in the First World is well-to-do today.  For Question #2, I'm utterly stumped.

(22 COMMENTS)
 •  0 comments  •  flag
Share on Twitter
Published on March 01, 2014 15:21

February 27, 2014

Wolfers Responds on Happiness, by Bryan Caplan

Justin Wolfers kindly responded to my recent post.  His thoughts, reprinted with his permission.


Interesting, fun, provocative, and well written.  Your
math looks to be right to me.





Some thoughts:



1. I'm not sure that controlling for confounds necessarily
would reduce the causal effect of income.  (My prior is similar to yours,
but I haven't thought through the issue enough).



2. I actually think 0.35 is pretty big.  Said another
way, it's big enough that it can explain why people in Burundi are at 3.5/10 on
a happiness scale, and Americans are at 8/10.  My interpretation is that
big gaps in happiness are easily explained by big gaps in income.  So why
do we interpret things differently?



a. I think raising happiness by a standard deviation is
huge.  Basically I see incredibly miserable people and incredibly happy
people all around me.  Moreover, if you think there's measurement error in
happiness, then the standard deviation in measured happiness is even bigger
(and you are talking about raising someone's measured happiness by one measured
standard deviation).



b. The other way of saying this is that it doesn't matter
that the effect of income on happiness is "small": if there exist
massive disparatives in income, then a small coefficient can have a big effect.
 And I think there exist massive disparaties in income (and these largely
explain the massive disparaties in happiness).



3. In my careful moments, I see my data as a shocking
refutation of whether money has no effect on happiness.  In my
less-guarded moments, I see it as a refutation of whether money has little effect
on happiness.



4. Your final thought experiment ("an extra
$820,585" is clever).  But it is just as interesting of a thought
experiment in the opposite direction: If I raised your income from $3,000
(roughly the average income in the US at the turn of the century) to $50k, I
would increase your happiness by one standard deviation.  How many people
would move from being "depressed" to OK? (If, for argument's sake,
depressed = bottom 5% in 1900, then depressed = % of people with z-score less
than 1.6.  Shift that distribution 1 standard deviation to the right, and
the proportion who are depressed = % of people with z-score 1 less than 1.6,
which is 0.5%. So we would nearly eliminate depression.)





But, as always, really interesting stuff, and great fodder
for the blog.





One more thought: The claim made by some that money matters
less than we think and hence we should focus less on it, always struck me as
important, and plausible, and one that my evidence is silent on.





J.



(6 COMMENTS)
 •  0 comments  •  flag
Share on Twitter
Published on February 27, 2014 21:05

February 26, 2014

Crude Materialism versus the Wolfers Equation , by Bryan Caplan

Suppose you're a crude materialist who believes that money
is the secret to happiness.  You're estimating an equation of the form:




Happiness (in Standard Deviations) = a + b * ln(income)



How big should you expect b to be?  Well, you'd probably think that
increasing income by 100% would increase happiness by at least a full
standard deviation.  Since ln(2)=.69, doubling income corresponds to a .69
log-dollar increase.  So you should expect to see something like:



Happiness (in Standard Deviations) = a + 1.44 * ln(income)



At the other extreme,  suppose you're a hard-line
Epicurean
who believes that human beings instantly acclimate to their
financial circumstances.  Then you'd expect to find something like:



Happiness (in Standard Deviations) = a + 0 * ln(income)



Last week Justin Wolfers came to GMU to present the best available individual,
cross-national, and over-time evidence on income
and happiness
.  After exploring a wide range of data sets, he
gleefully presented the answer:



Happiness (in Standard Deviations) = a + .35 * ln(income)



As usual, Wolfers' work was both careful and thorough.  But what does it
mean?  Most people interpret Wolfers' findings as a shocking refutation of
everyone who thinks that money has little effect on happiness.  Wolfers
largely embraced this take.  But should he?



I think not.  If you picture a continuum with Epicureanism at 0, and crude
materialism at 1, Wolfers stands at .24.  According to his results, the
effect of income on happiness, though positive, is small.



Not convinced?  Consider: Wolfers' result implies that to raise happiness
by one standard deviation, you have to raise income by 1/.35=2.86 log
points.  How much is that exactly?  In percentage terms, that's
(e^2.86)-1 - an increase of  1,640%.  So if you currently earn
$50,000, Wolfers' coefficient implies you'd need an extra $820,585 per year
to durably increase your happiness by one lousy standard deviation.  In
math, that's not "zero effect of income on happiness."  But in
English, it basically is.



Still not convinced?  Remember that Wolfers deliberately refrains from
controlling for confounding variables, so the true effect of income on
happiness is almost certainly even smaller than it looks.



The view that money has a major effect on happiness is ideologically convenient
for me.  But it goes against first-hand experience, the wisdom of the
ages, and the rightly interpreted empirical evidence.  So to hell with
ideological convenience.

(7 COMMENTS)
 •  0 comments  •  flag
Share on Twitter
Published on February 26, 2014 21:07

February 25, 2014

The Singaporean Path to Cosmopolitanism, by Bryan Caplan

Singapore has one of the most open immigration polices in the world.  But these policies do not currently enjoy popular support.  According to the World Values Survey, Singaporeans seem more anti-immigration than Americans:
Only 4% of Singaporeans favour open borders, and just 24% are willing to
admit immigrants "as long as jobs [are] available"; the comparable
numbers in the United States are 12.4% and 44.8%...
Fortunately, Singaporean elites are very pro-immigration, and the Singaporean electorate treats their elites with great deference.  Hence the Singaporean government's official long-run plan:
Foreigners now make up about 38 percent of the total population of 5.3 million. In 1990, that figure was 14 percent, when the total population was around 3 million.


Last year, a government policy paper called for the population to
increase a further 30 percent by 2030, to 6.9 million, at which time
immigrants would account for nearly half of the island's population.
Contrary to popular mythology, Singapore is a democracy.  It's conceivable that populist pressures will reverse Singapore's cosmopolitan course, as in Switzerland.  But I'll bet against it.  As immigration keeps rising, so will the social pressure against nativist complaining.  Deprived of social support, nativist sentiment will atrophy as well.  By the time Singaporean natives become a minority in their own country, nativist hold-outs won't lament "the country they lost."  They'll be too busy pretending they were never nativists in the first place.

(11 COMMENTS)
 •  0 comments  •  flag
Share on Twitter
Published on February 25, 2014 21:07

How Welfare Hurts Walmart, by Bryan Caplan

Walmart's critics often argue that food stamps, Medicaid, and other poverty programs subsidize its labor force.  Since government pays a big part of its workers' living expenses, Walmart doesn't have to.  Is this true?

As long as non-workers remain eligible for poverty programs, the answer is no.  This is basic supply-and-demand.  When the government offers free stuff to people with low incomes, the marginal benefit of work falls - and so does labor supply.  When labor supply falls, hours of work go down, and wages rise.  This could be very nice from the point of view of Walmart's workers.  From the point of view of Walmart's stockholders however, it's bad.

Not convinced?  Ask yourself: "If I ran Walmart, would I favor higher unemployment benefits?"  Of course not.  Why not?  Because higher unemployment benefits make it easier to not apply for a job at Walmart.  The same goes for any government program that makes idleness less unpalatable.

Once you grasp why standard welfare programs hurt Walmart, you are ready to search for counter-examples.  Is there any government program that actually increases labor supply?  Indeed there is: the Earned Income Tax Credit.  To benefit from this program, you have to work.  The more you work, the larger your tax credit.  When the EITC goes up, the marginal benefit of work rises - and so does labor supply.  This doesn't mean that Walmart is the sole beneficiary of the EITC; unless labor demand is perfectly inelastic, workers capture some of the program's benefits too.  But from Walmart's point of view, a bigger EITC is better.

HT: Perry Metzger

(25 COMMENTS)
 •  0 comments  •  flag
Share on Twitter
Published on February 25, 2014 07:17

February 23, 2014

The Minimum Wage vs. Welfare: Band-Aid or Salt?, by Bryan Caplan

Peter Thiel entertains what economists would call a "second-best" argument in favor of raising the minimum wage:
"In theory, I'm against it, because people should have the freedom to
contract at whatever wage they'd like to have. But in practice, I think
the alternative to higher minimum wage is that people simply end up
going on welfare.''


"And so, given how low the minimum wage is -- and how generous the
welfare benefits are -- you have a marginal tax rate that's on the order
of 100 percent, and people are actually trapped in this sort of welfare
state."


"So I actually think that it's a very out of the box idea -- but it's
something one should consider seriously, given all the other distorted
incentives that exist."
Is he right?  Maybe.  A key insight of welfare economics is that one inefficient policy can counter-act another inefficient policy.  But does this insight apply in this particular case?  Let's work through matters step by step.

First, imagine laissez-faire.  There's no welfare and no minimum wage.  The low-skilled labor market looks just like this:

Figure 1: Low-Skilled Labor Market Under Laissez-Faire
mw1.jpg
There's no involuntary unemployment, and the big black dot reveals the wage and quantity of labor.

Now imagine adding a minimum wage - but no welfare - to the mix.

Figure 2: Low-Skilled Labor Market With Minimum Wage But No Welfare
mw2a.jpg
The big black dot still reveals the wage and quantity of labor.  Thanks to the minimum wage, though, there's now a lot of involuntary unemployment, marked in red.  This is true despite the fact that the minimum wage increases the incentive to work.  Why?  Because the minimum wage also reduces the incentive to hire!  Since a deal only happens if both demanders and suppliers of labor consent, the quantity of hours worked is the smaller of quantity demanded and quantity supplied.

Under laissez-faire, any able-bodied worker can get a job and stand on
his own two feet.  The minimum wage deprives the unfortunate workers
shown in red of their ability to support themselves.  Given this involuntary unemployment, the case for welfare is suddenly easier to make.  What happens if the government in its mercy puts the unemployed on the dole? 

Figure 3: Low-Skilled Labor Market With Minimum Wage and Welfare mw3.jpgThe answer may surprise you.  The supply of labor falls to S', of course, because free money makes workers less eager to work.  But unless welfare is ample enough to push the market-clearing wage above the legal minimum wage, welfare has no effect on the wage or quantity of hours worked!  Why not?  Because thanks to the minimum wage, jobs are rationed.  There's still a line of eager applicants even if the marginal payoff for work declines. 

With a binding minimum wage, the only clear-cut effect of welfare is to transform involuntary unemployment into voluntary unemployment.  That's why the red line shrinks: Some - though not all - of the workers who craved a job at the minimum wage now shrug, "Eh, now that I've got free money, why interview?"

On Thiel's story, though, Figure 3 doesn't fit the contemporary labor market.  He claims that welfare is now so generous that workers no longer desire minimum wage jobs.  Diagrammatically:

Figure 4: Low-Skilled Labor Market With Minimum Wage and High Welfare
mw4a.jpg
Notice: Sufficiently high welfare makes the minimum wage irrelevant.  The market now clears at the intersection of the old demand curve D and the new supply curve S''.  Since the intersection exceeds the minimum, the minimum has no effect.  Thanks to welfare, employment is low.  But whatever unemployment you see is voluntary. 

OK, now we're ready to see if Thiel's story makes sense.  Figure 4 roughly describes the world he thinks we're in.  What would happen if, swayed by Thiel's argument, government raises the minimum wage to counteract welfare's disincentive effects?

Figure 5: Low-Skilled Labor Market With High Minimum Wage and High Welfare
mw5a.jpg
The answer, as Figure 5 clearly shows, is utterly orthodox: wages rise, employment falls, and involuntary unemployment revives.  How is this possible?  Simple.  Generous welfare benefits do nothing to vitiate the truism that the minimum wage simultaneously raises the incentive to work and cuts the incentive to hire.  And as usual, a deal only happens if both demanders and suppliers consent.  The market therefore goes to the intersection of quantity demanded and the new minimum wage, with unemployment shown in red. 

The lesson: When the minimum wage causes involuntary unemployment, raising welfare can serve as a band-aid for the labor market.  Workers deprived of the right to provide for themselves can subsist on government money.  Yet when welfare convinces people to abandon honest toil, raising the minimum wage is no band-aid.  Instead, raising the minimum wage salts the wounds.  The reason, to repeat: While a higher minimum wage does indeed make workers more eager to work, it also automatically makes employers less eager to hire. 

I have great respect for Peter Thiel, but his concession to minimum wage advocates is confused.  While some inefficient policies can offset the effects of other inefficient policies, the minimum wage is not such a policy.  It doesn't matter if welfare is high, low, or non-existent.  The minimum wage causes unemployment by making marginal workers unprofitable to employ.



(8 COMMENTS)
 •  0 comments  •  flag
Share on Twitter
Published on February 23, 2014 21:46

February 20, 2014

Ambition Revisited, by Bryan Caplan

I just ran across some more striking evidence that ambition really matters.  James Rosenbaum's "College-For-All: Do Students Understand What College Demands?" (Social Psychology of Education, 1998) shows degree completion as a function of high school students' GPA and educational aspirations.

Exhibit A: Percentage of high school seniors who plan to get a BA who successfully do so.

collegeforall.jpg

Exhibit B: Percentage of high school seniors who plan to get an AA who successfully do so.

collegeforall2.jpg

The simplest reading of the evidence is that getting a BA is easier than getting an AA!  After all, holding high school GPA constant, students are vastly more likely to complete the BA.  Over two-thirds of A-students who plan to get a BA succeed; less than half of A-students who plan to get an AA succeed.  This pattern extends all the way down to the weakest students.

A better interpretation, though, is that seniors who say they want a BA have a lot more ambition than their peers.  As a result, they are - holding grades fixed - markedly more likely to achieve their goal despite its intrinsic difficulty.  Seniors who say they only want an AA, in contrast, simultaneously aim low and fall short.

This probably doesn't mean that students can improve their prospects merely by mouthing the words, "I plan to get a BA."  The reasonable interpretation, rather, is that people who place a high value on conventional success are much more likely to achieve it.  A B student who says, "I want a BA" is as likely to cross his personal finish line as an A student who says, "I want an AA."  And as far as I know, no estimate of the return to education properly adjusts for this factor.

(0 COMMENTS)
 •  0 comments  •  flag
Share on Twitter
Published on February 20, 2014 21:04

February 19, 2014

Desert versus Identity, by Bryan Caplan

When moderns read the Old Testament, they're often horrified by the gruesome collective punishments.  Mankind falls into wickedness, so God sends a flood to drown every man, women, and child on earth?*  Before the book is over, though, the prophets start singing a radically different tune:
[T]he son will not be made responsible for the evil-doing of the father,
or the father for the evil-doing of the son; the righteousness of the
upright will be on himself, and the evil-doing of the evil-doer on
himself.
                                             -Ezekiel 18:20
You can't judge a person for the actions of his father, sisters, neighbors, or people who share his hair color.  Instead, you must judge him for what he has personally done.  What moral truth could be more self-evident? 

Yet in practice, human beings' adherence to this moral truth remains iffy.  The main reason is clear: group identity.  When people judge members of their own groups, they accept an endless list of lame excuses.  When people judge members of other groups, they accept an endless list of ludicrous condemnations.

War crimes are a stark example.  Suppose a soldier from group X plainly murdered ten innocent civilians from group Y.  What do the people of X say?  "It was war."  "He just lost his buddy a month earlier."  "If you've never been in that situation, you can't judge."  "He was just following orders."  "His officer should have seen it coming." 

This absurd leniency reverses, of course, when members of group X judge some enemy Y's during wartime.  Although the individual Y's plainly never hurt a fly, they deserve to die!  "They started the
war; we're just finishing it."  "They leave us no choice."  "They would have done far worse to us."  "What about the innocent X's the Y's killed?"  Never mind if the specific Y's on the chopping block are powerless peons, hapless conscripts, or defenseless children.  They brought their deaths on themselves by belonging to a team they are metaphysically unable to quit.
 
We see the same farce when people decide whether someone deserves his poverty.  If the pauper belongs to group X, members of group X loathe to blame him.  The pauper is routinely drunk?  Well, that's an understandable response to an unjust society, bad upbringing, or despair.  The pauper spends half his money on cable?  Well, in our society cable's a necessity.  He got fired because he could barely read or add?  Our public schools failed him - even if his teachers reliably showed up and did their jobs - and the student was smoking in the boys' room.

If the pauper belongs to an out-group, in contrast, members of group X will fault him for the most absurd reasons.  The best job he can get pays $1 a day?  He should have gotten himself a better education.  The government's teachers rarely even show up to class?  That's what you get when you elect a government with crummy economic policies.  His government is a dictatorship?  That's what happens when you forget that vigilance is liberty's eternal price.  What about the obvious fact that all of these problems - unlike alcohol and cable consumption - are largely or entirely outside the control of one impoverished individual?  Blank-out.

Human beings evolved in small bands.  Group identity - and group identity's tendency to corrupt our sense of justice -  is in our DNA.  Once you learn this harsh truth, though, you can, should, and must compensate for your immoral urges.  Review your judgments of out-group members for draconian harshness.  Review your judgments of in-group members - yourself included - for maudlin absolution.  You won't make a lot of friends, but you will be a better person.

* Noah's family excepted, of course.

(6 COMMENTS)
 •  0 comments  •  flag
Share on Twitter
Published on February 19, 2014 21:05

Bryan Caplan's Blog

Bryan Caplan
Bryan Caplan isn't a Goodreads Author (yet), but they do have a blog, so here are some recent posts imported from their feed.
Follow Bryan Caplan's blog with rss.