Edward Feser's Blog, page 66
June 3, 2017
The curious case of Pope Francis and the “new natural lawyers”

Another example is capital punishment. Scripture, the Fathers and Doctors of the Church, and a long line of popes have consistently affirmed that capital punishment can be legitimate in principle. Indeed, some popes have taught that it is contrary to Catholic orthodoxy to deny that capital punishment can in principle be legitimate. Even Pope John Paul II, who famously opposed capital punishment in practice, was careful explicitly to affirm that it can be legitimate at least in principle. It has, however, become the standard view among the “new natural lawyers” that capital punishment is in fact always and intrinsically wrong, wrong even in principle and not merely in practice under modern circumstances. Grisez started to promote this idea around 1970, and his followers have argued that the Catholic Church could reverse her consistent teaching on this subject and adopt Grisez’s novel doctrine instead.
This is delusional and dangerous. In our book By Man Shall His Blood Be Shed: A Catholic Defense of Capital Punishment , Joseph Bessette and I show, we think conclusively, that the legitimacy in principle of capital punishment is in fact an irreformable teaching of the Church. (Joe and I briefly summarized some key points in an article at Catholic World Report last year, but I urge the interested reader to consult chapter 2 of the book, which devotes well over 100 pages of documentation and analysis to the subject.) Any pope who tried to reverse this teaching would by that very fact put himself in that small company of popes who have taught doctrinal error, which Catholic teaching allows is possible when a pope is not speaking ex cathedra. He would also severely damage the credibility both of the Church and of himself. If Scripture, the Fathers and Doctors of the Church, and all previous popes could all be so wrong for so long about something that serious, why should anyone trust what the Church says about any other topic? And why should anyone trust a pope who contradicted his predecessors in this way? If they could all get things so badly wrong, why believe him?
Pope Francis and capital punishment
It might appear, however, that in Pope Francis, the “new natural lawyers” have found a pontiff who might be willing to move in their radically abolitionist direction. For the pope has sometimes made remarks that seem, at least at first glance and when read in isolation, to condemn capital punishment as intrinsically unjust.
To be sure, as Joe and I argue in our book, when read carefully it is clear that Pope Francis has not in fact quite said this. We devote a fair amount of space to analyzing the pope’s statements about capital punishment (see pp. 183-196), and we argue that when all his remarks are taken account of, it is evident that he does not in substance move beyond what Pope John Paul II taught.
However, rhetorically he has several times gone beyond John Paul II. For example, in 2015 he stated that “justice is never reached by killing a human being” and in 2016 he said that “the commandment ‘thou shalt not kill’ has absolute value and pertains to the innocent as well as the guilty” and that “even a criminal has the inviolable right to life” (emphasis added). Some of his remarks have been even more extreme. For example, in the 2015 statement he went so far as approvingly to quote a remark he attributed to Dostoevsky to the effect that “to kill a murderer is a punishment incomparably worse than the crime itself”(!)
Pope Francis has also not confined his negative remarks to capital punishment. He has several times also indicated that he regards even life imprisonment as immoral. For example, in 2014 he stated that “a life sentence is just a death penalty in disguise” and implied that opponents of the latter must therefore oppose the former as well. He repeated this in his 2015 remarks, criticizing sentences to life imprisonment as “hidden death sentences.” Not only does this go far beyond anything Pope John Paul II or any other previous pope said, it also conflicts with what other Catholic opponents of capital punishment say. For example, in a 2005 document the United States Conference of Catholic Bishops recommended “life without the possibility of parole” as an alternative to capital punishment.
Again, as Joe and I show in the book, Pope Francis has also said things that point away from a condemnation of capital punishment as intrinsically immoral. For example, in the 2015 statement he also says that the “elimination” of an aggressor is sometimes “necessary,” and that “today capital punishment is unacceptable,” indicating that it was legitimate in the past and under different circumstances.
Then there is the fact that some of his remarks are soextreme that a charitable reader would have to conclude that the pope is in general speaking with rhetorical flourish rather than intending to make careful doctrinal remarks. Consider the statement that the death penalty is “incomparably worse than” the crimes for which an offender might be executed. Taken at face value, this remark is preposterous, indeed obscene. To take just one example, Ted Bundy murdered fourteen women, routinely raped and tortured his victims, and mutilated and even engaged in necrophilia with their bodies. He was executed in the electric chair, a method of killing that takes only a few moments. Does any sane person really believe that executing Bundy was “incomparably worse than” what Bundy himself did?
Or consider the claim that life imprisonment ought also to be abolished. Is the pope telling us that serial killers and mass murderers like Charles Manson, Richard Allen Davis, Khalid Sheikh Mohammed, et al. ought to be let out of prison? Presumably not. But then, what exactly does he mean? Presumably he is merely expressing in a rhetorically extreme way the view that life imprisonment can be morally problematic, even if it is not always and in itself wrong.
If these remarks are to be read as mere rhetorical flourishes, though, then it is plausible that the pope’s other remarks about capital punishment are to be read as rhetorical, rather than as expressions of the view that capital punishment is always and in principle wrong. Again, Joe Bessette and I defend this interpretation at length in our book.
All the same, it would by no means be surprising if “new natural lawyers” appealed to at least some of Pope Francis’s statements on capital punishment as evidence of papal support for their extreme abolitionist position. Yet to my knowledge, they have not done this. They have not said: “Pope Francis has now taught that even a criminal’s right to life is inviolable and that the fifth commandment applies to the guilty as well as to the innocent! This is nothing less than a papal seal of approval on what we ‘new natural lawyers’ have been saying for decades!”
This is very odd. Critics have for years been accusing NNLT advocates of contradicting irreformable Catholic doctrine and of taking Pope John Paul II’s teaching on capital punishment in an extreme direction that he did not take it himself. Now Pope Francis has, at least on a surface reading, given them ammunition. Yet they have not used it. Why not?
Pope Francis and the “new natural lawyers”
The answer, I conjecture, is that the “new natural lawyers” have found Pope Francis’s remarks on other doctrinal matters to be so distressing that they are reluctant to appeal to him on this one.
Consider first Grisez’s response to the pope’s famous 2013 interview with Fr. Antonio Spadaro (the one in which the pope said, among other things, that the Church shouldn’t be “obsessed with the transmission of a disjointed multitude of doctrines to be imposed insistently“). Commenting on one of the remarks the pope made in that interview, Grisez said:
[I]f it was suggested by a spirit, it was not the Holy Spirit, for it is bound to confuse and mislead.
I’m afraid that Pope Francis has failed to consider carefully enough the likely consequences of letting loose with his thoughts in a world that will applaud being provided with such help in subverting the truth it is his job to guard as inviolable and proclaim with fidelity. For a long time he has been thinking these things. Now he can say them to the whole world – and he is self-indulgent enough to take advantage of the opportunity with as little care as he might unburden himself with friends after a good dinner and plenty of wine.
End quote. That’s pretty strong language – and note that Grisez made these remarks even before Pope Francis made his most controversial utterances.
Coming to those, consider next the pope’s remarks last year about the use of contraception as a way of dealing with the Zika virus. Two NNLT advocates, Tollefsen and Brugger, have argued (plausibly in my view) that the pope’s statements are morally problematic and cannot be reconciled with Catholic teaching on contraception.
Then there is the problematic nature of Pope Francis’s statements in Amoris Laetitia and elsewhere about divorce, remarriage, and Holy Communion (about which I have written not too long ago). Brugger has raised worries about these statements in a series of articles (here, here, here, and here). Grisez and Finnis have called on Pope Francis to condemn certain errors that are being propagated in the name of Amoris.
It may be, then, that the “new natural lawyers” have come to regard Pope Francis’s Magisterium as too problematic in general to be useful to appeal to in defense of their position on capital punishment. That is speculation on my part, but it would explain the otherwise puzzling failure of NNLT writers to trumpet the pope’s statements on that subject. There is rich irony here. For decades NNLT advocates have been waiting for a pope who would adopt their extreme never-even-in-principle position on the death penalty. Yet when they finally get a pope who at least arguably comes close to this, he ends up saying things on other topics that they find highly alarming. It must be very frustrating for them.
New unnatural loopholes
I can’t say I feel their pain, however. For there is another rich irony here – namely that the “new natural lawyers’” position on capital punishment is, frankly, far more obviouslyin conflict with Catholic tradition than anything Pope Francis has said. Not to put too fine a point on it, it takes real chutzpah for writers whose position implies that scripture, the Fathers and Doctors of the Church, and 2000 years of papal teaching have all been gravely in error to complain that Pope Francis has broken with Catholic tradition!
The pope has, after all, claimed that his most controversial remarks are perfectly in harmony with tradition, and to some extent has even tried to justify this claim. For example, he cited an alleged policy of Pope Paul VI when attempting to justify his remarks about Zika and contraception. Amoriscites Gaudium et Spes in support when it appears to suggest that the good of the children produced by adulterous unions might be endangered if “certain expressions of intimacy are lacking.” I do not say that these particular appeals to tradition are plausible – I think they are not plausible – but again, it is at least claimed that there is no rupture with tradition.
Compare that with Brugger’s book Capital Punishment and Roman Catholic Moral Tradition , which is by far the most detailed treatment of the subject written from a NNLT point of view. It is a very curious document. In particular, it is striking how much Brugger concedes to those who claim that the NNLT position is a radical break with traditional Catholic teaching.
For example, Brugger admits that the attempts of theologians who oppose capital punishment to reinterpret passages like Genesis 9:6 (“Whoever sheds the blood of man, by man shall his blood be shed; for God made man in his own image”) are unconvincing. He admits that the passage poses a “problem” for positions like his own, which is “left standing” even given the creative exegesis of modern biblical scholars.
While some have claimed that Church Fathers like Tertullian and Lactantius were opposed even in principle to capital punishment, Brugger also admits that this is not the case. Indeed, he admits that there was a “Patristic consensus” on the legitimacy in principle of capital punishment (even if some Fathers opposed it in practice).
Brugger admits that when Pope Innocent III required the Waldensian heretics to affirm, as a matter of Catholic orthodoxy, that capital punishment can be inflicted without mortal sin, what the pope meant is that the punishment itself can be legitimate. Brugger thereby disagrees with Grisez, who has tried to reinterpret Innocent III’s teaching as concerned only with subjective culpability for the act of execution rather than with the moral status of the act itself.
Brugger admits that modern abolitionism has its roots in philosophical ideas and social movements hostile to Catholicism, such as the thought of Voltaire, Hume, and Bentham, in social contract theory and utilitarianism, in the loss of belief in an afterlife and consequent emphasis on prolonging this life, and in Enlightenment and secularist thinking in general. He admits that the experience of Catholic pastors shows that the prospect of execution often leads offenders to repentance and conversion.
Brugger admits that even Pope John Paul II, despite his opposition in practice to most executions, explicitly taught that capital punishment is legitimate in principle. He admits that what he calls the “plain-face interpretation” of the 1997 update of the Catechism of Catholic Church does not support even the claim that a development of doctrine has taken place, much less a reversal of past teaching. In the new edition of his book, Brugger also admits that Pope Benedict XVI would probably not agree with any attempt to construct from John Paul II’s teaching a more radically abolitionist position (as Brugger tries to do).
In general, Brugger admits that scripture, tradition, and the history of papal teaching have consistently supported the legitimacy in principle of capital punishment, and compiles a mountain of evidence to that effect. Rare is the author who so thoroughly if inadvertently undermines his own case.
And yet he does try to make that case. That is to say, Brugger attempts, in the face of all this evidence to the contrary, to show that the NNLT thesis that capital punishment is always and intrinsically wrong, wrong even in principle and not merely in practice, is compatible with Catholicism. The attempt involves two basic lines of argument. First, Brugger claims that while the Church has always taught that capital punishment is legitimate in principle, she has not done so in a strictly irreformable way. Second, he claims that even though Pope John Paul II did not explicitly teach that capital punishment is immoral in principle (and indeed explicitly taught the opposite), such a teaching is nevertheless implicitin some of the things he said.
Now, in By Man Shall His Blood Be Shed, Joe and I examine these lines of argument in detail, and we show that they are completely without merit. Indeed, you will find in our book the most thorough response yet given to Brugger and other NNLT writers on capital punishment.
I direct readers interested in a critique of the NNLT position to our book, then. The point I want to emphasize for present purposes is this: By Brugger’s own admission, the NNLT position on capital punishment is radically discontinuouswith what the Church has traditionally taught, has not yet been shown to be reconcilable with scripture, and requires departing from the “plain-face interpretation” even of the magisterial texts most favorable to it. How is that any better than what the “new natural lawyers” find troubling in some of Pope Francis’s statements (which at least claim to be in continuity with tradition)? How can it be permissible for NNLT advocates to ignore the “plain-face interpretation” of John Paul II’s statements in Evangelium vitae in favor of some purportedly deeper new doctrine vis-à-vis capital punishment, if it is impermissible for even a pope to ignore the “plain-face interpretation” of John Paul II’s statements in Familaris consortio in favor of a purportedly deeper new understanding of Holy Communion for the divorced and remarried? Why do the “new natural lawyers” get a pass if Pope Francis doesn’t?
In fact what NNLT advocates worry that they see in Pope Francis and his defenders is something they have for decades been practicing themselves – “lawyering” in the sense of looking for loopholes in Catholic tradition by which some novel doctrine might be introduced into it, and by which the novelty might be acquitted of the charge of heterodoxy on a technicality. On the back cover of the first edition of Brugger’s book, a blurb from Grisez tells us that Brugger “defends the proposition that the Catholic Church could teach that capital punishment is always morally wrong” (emphasis added). But looking for ways by which the Church “could teach” such-and-such is a very odd way of doing Catholic theology. One would have thought that the idea was rather to find out what the Church doesin fact teach. After all, as the First Vatican Council declared:
For the Holy Spirit was promised to the successors of Peter not so that they might, by his revelation, make known some new doctrine, but that, by his assistance, they might religiously guard and faithfully expound the revelation or deposit of faith transmitted by the apostles.
The theologian’s business, the “new natural lawyers” would rightly warn us, is not to remake Catholicism in the image of Walter Kasper’s personal theology. But neither is it to remake Catholicism in the image of Germain Grisez’s personal theology. The disease the NNLT writers diagnose is one they have played no small part in spreading themselves.
Published on June 03, 2017 16:52
May 25, 2017
Catholic Herald on capital punishment

Published on May 25, 2017 18:53
When is a university not a university?

Published on May 25, 2017 18:34
May 23, 2017
Peters on By Man Shall His Blood Be Shed

Since I first saw it in galley form several months ago I have been impatiently awaiting the [book’s] publication… Well, my copy just arrived in the mail.
Defenders of the death penalty for certain heinous offenses need no encouragement from me to study this book, of course, but, from now on, opponents of the death penalty who do not address the arguments set out by Feser & Bessette really have nothing useful to contribute to the debate.After reading said galley, Prof. Peters provided an endorsement for the book, the full text of which is as follows:
Feser and Bessette’s defense of capital punishment is a triumph of truth over platitude, of fact over fiction, of argument over emotion. In response to recent condemnations of the death penalty issued by various ecclesiastics, Feser and Bessette calmly and methodically set forth the philosophical, Scriptural, doctrinal, and sociological arguments grounding the Catholic Church’s hitherto unquestioned – and ultimately unquestionable – support for the death penalty when it is justly administered. Defenders of capital punishment will find in these pages persuasive arguments upholding the proper exercise of this momentous state power and opponents of the death penalty will see their challenges accurately depicted and soberly answered. From this point on, all contributions to the capital punishment debate, especially as conducted by and among Catholics, must incorporate the work of Feser and Bessette or risk irrelevance.
Joe and I thank Prof. Peters for his very kind words. If you’re not familiar with Prof. Peters’ fine blog, you should be.
Interested readers can find other endorsements of the book at my main web page.
Published on May 23, 2017 21:34
May 19, 2017
Wrath and its daughters

We are also angry at actions that are less grave than such crimes are but that are still in a general sense unjust. For example, someone cuts you off on the freeway or insults you, and you are naturally angry because the person unjustly endangered you or characterized you in a pejorative way that in your judgment you do not merit. Your child refuses to eat his vegetables or do his homework, and you are naturally angry because he is not doing what is good for him and not submitting to your legitimate authority over him. The anger in these cases, no less than in the case of anger at criminal offenses, is directed at injustice in the broad sense of a disorder in things, of things not being the way they ought to be. Anger is nature’s way of prodding you to do something to set things right.
As Aquinas says in On Evil, quoting St. John Chrysostom, “if there be no anger, teaching is bootless, the judicial process undermined, and crimes unchecked.” Accordingly, Aquinas concludes, “some anger is good and necessary” (p. 373, Regan translation). The absence of anger in cases where it is called for is, for that reason, a moral defect, and a habit or tendency to respond to injustices with insufficient anger is a vice. As Aquinas writes in the Summa:
Anger… [is] a simple movement of the will, whereby one inflicts punishment, not through passion, but in virtue of a judgment of the reason: and thus without doubt lack of anger is a sin…
Hence the movement of anger in the sensitive appetite cannot be lacking altogether, unless the movement of the will be altogether lacking or weak. Consequently lack of the passion of anger is also a vice, even as the lack of movement in the will directed to punishment by the judgment of reason…
The lack of anger is a sign that the judgment of reason is lacking.
End quote. The sin Aquinas speaks of is manifest today in those who are excessively lenient toward criminals, those who are suspicious of the very idea of punishment, those whose knee-jerk response to even the most horrific crimes is always to talk only of forgiveness and mercy whether or not the evildoer is repentant, and so forth. Such a reflexive attitude is not the Christian attitude but rather a crude caricature of the Christian attitude.
What Christianity condemns, and what Aquinas condemns, is not anger per se but rather the opposite vice of excesswhere anger is concerned. Anger becomes disordered and sinful when the passion is so strong that it overwhelms reason, when the punishment the angry person seeks to inflict on the evildoer is out of proportion to the offense, when the person at whom one is angry is in fact innocent of injustice, when the angry person acts out of hatred rather than justice, and so forth. And habituation to disordered anger is a vice.
If deficiency in anger is common today, excess is of course no less common. Bizarrely, the defect and the excess sometimes exist in one and the same person. Consider that curious character familiar from modern political life, the militant pacifist. For even the worst murderers and dictators, he has nothing but compassion. Their sins, he assures us, are regrettable but understandable – a result of bad upbringing or weakness of will, an overreaction to social injustice or American imperialism, or what have you. In sharp contrast, for defenders of capital punishment or just war, the militant pacifist has nothing but venom. He attributes to them only the basest motives – bloodthirstiness, hatred, political calculation, war profiteering, and so forth.
It never occurs to him how deeply irrational and incoherent is this combination of attitudes. For example, if the militant pacifist is going to try his best to show mercy to and understand the motives of murderers and the like, how much more should he show mercy and understanding to defenders of capital punishment? (“They mean well, they’re just misguided!”) Or if he is peremptorily going to condemn the latter as hateful and bloodthirsty, how much more peremptorily should he condemn those who kill innocent people?
(My favorite example of this sort of incoherence is the sentiment sometimes expressed by critics of the doctrine of hell to the effect that the only people who deserve to go to hell are people who think some people deserve to go to hell. Since critics who say that are thereby acknowledging that they themselves think some people deserve hell – namely those who think some people deserve it – these critics are implicitly including themselvesamong those worthy of hell!)
Illumination is provided by Aquinas’s account of the daughtersof the vice of wrath – the further disorders of the soul which follow upon disordered anger – of which there are six. The first two have to do with disorders of thought, the next three with disorders of speech, and the last with disorders of action. (See Summa Theologiae II-II.158.7 and On Evil XII.5.)
The first daughter is what Aquinas calls “indignation,” which (as Aquinas says in the Summa) is directed at “the person with whom a man is angry, and whom he deems unworthy” (emphasis added). In On Evil, Aquinas adds that “angry persons contemplating the harm inflicted on them magnify the injustice in their minds” (p. 387). The idea here seems to be that a person habituated to wrath tends to turn over and over in his mind the notions of how depraved are the people against whom he is angry and how graveare their imagined injustices. He creates fantasy enemies who are more evil in their character and their actions than any real world opponents are, and directs his rage at the latter while mistaking them for the former.
The second daughter is what Aquinas refers to in the Summaas “swelling of the mind,” and in On Evilhe says that this is manifest in angry persons who “mull over different ways and means whereby they can avenge themselves.” Whereas indignation focuses on the imagined depravity of the objects of one’s anger, swelling of the mind focuses on the harms that might be inflicted on these supposed evildoers.
The third daughter of wrath is referred to by Aquinas in the Summa as “’clamor,’ which denotes disorderly and confused speech.” Think of the person who is so filled with rage that he cannot get a coherent thought or line of argument out, but simply rants uncontrollably.
The fourth daughter of wrath is “contumely” or harsh and insulting language. Think of the person so consumed by anger that he characterizes his enemies in unjust and uncharitable ways. Contumely is essentially the verbal expression of what Aquinas calls the wrathful person’s “indignation” and “swelling of mind.” (Note that, just as anger is not per se bad, neither is harsh or insulting speech per se bad. Christ famously characterized the Pharisees as “a brood of vipers” and “whited sepulchers.” What is bad is harsh or insulting language that is unmerited and/or flows from excessive passion rather than reason.)
The fifth daughter of wrath is blasphemy. Like contumely, it involves a kind of injurious speech, but in this case directed toward God rather than other human beings. (Needless to say, this daughter will follow from disordered anger only if God is the object of the anger.)
The sixth daughter of wrath is “quarreling.” The wrathful person, naturally, is prone to give expression to his disorders of thought not only in his speech, but also by picking fights with various enemies or imagined enemies.
Now, as with lust, wrath and its daughters are associated with pleasure, and as with lust, this pleasure has a tendency to “lock” or “glue” the person exhibiting the vice onto his disordered behavior. This is harder to see in the case of wrath than in the case of lust, because anger is directed toward the rectification of perceived injustice, and the perception of injustice is unpleasant. However, the hope of rectifying injustice is pleasant. As Aquinas writes, “anger is always accompanied by hope, wherefore it causes pleasure” and “the movement of anger has a… tendency… to vengeance… which it desires and hopes for as being a good, wherefore it takes pleasure in it.” What Aquinas calls “indignation,” “swelling of the mind,” contumely and the like can therefore be pleasant, and thus addictive to the one exhibiting them, deeply habituating his tendency toward disordered anger.
Taking account of the daughters of wrath, it is easy to see why the sort of person I have called the “militant pacifist” exhibits such non-pacific behavior. Anger, if one is not careful, can become disordered whatever its object. This is as true of people whose anger is directed toward capital punishment, war, or the like as it is of people angry over any other perceived injustice. With the “militant pacifist,” though, we get the paradoxical result that someone angry over what he regards as disordered anger in others comes himself to exhibit disordered anger precisely toward those others. He might become so obsessed with his cause that he falls into “indignation” in Aquinas’s sense, constructing in his mind a phantom enemy that is far more sinister than the real world people who disagree with him. He is led thereby into “clamor” and “contumely,” hurling insults and ranting and raving rather than soberly addressing the arguments of his opponents. And so forth.
Indeed, the “militant pacifist” may, ironically, be moreprone to fall victim to the daughters of wrath than other people are. The reason is this. Anger, again, is in itself good and natural to us. It is nature’s way of getting us to redress injustice by punishing evildoers. Now, some injustices are so extremely grave that nothing less than death would be a proportionate punishment. And some evildoers are so dangerous that nothing less than war can effectively counter them. Unsurprisingly, then, large numbers of people continue to support capital punishment and to believe that war is sometimes necessary to deal with evil regimes. Even in countries that have long ago abolished capital punishment, opinion polls sometimes show that a majority still support it, despite decades of propaganda directed against it.
In light of these facts, opponents of capital punishment, war, and the like are bound to be tempted to conclude that enormous numbers of their fellow citizens are simply depraved. (It does not occur to them that what is in fact going on is that widespread continued support for the death penalty and for just war reflects a residual grasp of the demands of the natural law.) Frustrated by the persistence and popularity of attitudes they regard as immoral, those of what I am calling a “militant pacifist” mindset are bound to become even angrierat these perceived injustices – with a spiral into wrath and its daughters being the sequel.
Moreover, precisely because the militant pacifist’s position is always bound to be a minority view (contrary as it is to human nature), it is tempting for the militant pacifist to think of himself as possessing greater virtue than most people. In particular, he is bound to think of himself as more merciful, more compassionate, more understanding than the great unwashed. Such self-righteousness can be intoxicating, and contribute to the sense of being “superior” that Aquinas, in On Evil, says is part of the psychology of “indignation” (p. 387).
Finally, precisely because he is so militantly opposed to the purported disordered anger of others, the militant pacifist is deluded into thinking that he, of all people, cannot be subject to that particular vice. He is utterly blind to the mercilessness and hatred he directs toward those whom he regards as merciless and hateful.
Published on May 19, 2017 19:15
May 11, 2017
Davies on evil suffered

Do you agree with Davies in saying that God does not directly bring about what he calls “evil suffered”? I want to agree, but yet I don’t know how to reconcile Davies’ position (and what seems to be Aquinas’ position) with God apparently directly willing the end of Ananias and Sapphira’s life in Acts 5, which obviously is an evil suffered. It doesn’t seem there is causality per accidens like Davies describes God’s causal activity when it comes to evil suffered (e.g., good of one thing curtailing the good of another).Before I answer the question, let me do some stage-setting by summarizing the views of Davies alluded to here. (See especially pp. 176-83 of Davies’ book for his own exposition.) Davies makes two relevant points about evil suffered. First, it is a privation rather than a positive reality. Second, it is not willed by God as an end in itself, but only as a concomitant of some good.
By way of illustration of these ideas, let’s suppose that in the course of giving a philosophy lecture, I begin to draw a circle on the marker board but do not complete it, so that the resulting figure looks like a C. The circle is a bad or defective circle, and insofar as I am the cause of it, what I have caused is therefore something that exhibits badness or defect. But strictly speaking, the badness does not amount to some positive feature I have put into the circle. Rather, it amounts to the absence of some feature that I could have put into it and that a complete circle would have had. The badness is a privation rather than a positive reality.
Strictly speaking, then, I have not caused any badness to exist. Rather, what I have done is simply refrained from causing all of the goodness that I could have caused to exist. The circle is good as far as it goes, but it doesn’t go all the way.
So, in that sense I have only caused what is good. But wouldn’t it have been better still to cause the rest of the circle to exist? All things being equal, it would have been, but suppose that the reason I refrained from completing it is that I judged that doing so was necessary in order to explain to my audience the notion of a privation. Then there would be an overall good situation – the generation of philosophical understanding in my audience – that was brought about in part precisely by my refraining from putting into the circle all the goodness that could have been in it. The defective circle, though bad, was an essential part of some larger good. And that is why I willed to refrain from completing it, rather than willing the defect in the circle for its own sake.
Now, for Davies, the instances of evil suffered that we find in the natural order of things are analogous to that. When a lamb is eaten by a lion, the damage to the lamb amounts to a set of privations – for example, the absence of a limb, flesh, or skin that is torn away. Though bad considered in itself, the damage also plays a necessary part of a larger good, namely the flourishing of the lion. Lions of their nature can’t be the kinds of things they are without hunting prey like lambs, so that having the good of there being lions presupposes the bad of lambs being killed. In causing a world in which lambs are eaten by lions, then, God does not cause evil as such. Rather, he causes a world in which certain goods (namely the good of lambs having all their limbs, flesh, etc. unmolested) are absent, and these privations are not willed by him for their own sake, but rather as a concomitant of the good of there being lions in existence.
So that’s the background to the reader’s question. And the question, again, is how the deaths of Ananias and Sapphira fit into this account of the nature of evil suffered. Recall that Davies’ main points about evil suffered are, first, that it is a privation rather than a positive reality, and second, that it is not willed by God as an end in itself, but only as a concomitant of some good. These deaths would, as the reader says, be instances of evil suffered. So do they fit Davies’ account?
It’s not hard to see how they fit the privation part of the account. Presumably the deaths of Ananias and Sapphira were simply a matter of the absence of continued divine concurrence with the operation of their vital processes. After all, nothing can operate for an instant unless God imparts causal power to it; hence to cause the death of a person, God need do no more than cease causing the person to live. The badness in this case (the deaths) amounts, as in the other cases, to the absence of a good (continued life).
Apparently the reader’s main concern is with how the scenario fits in with Davies’ second point, to the effect that an evil suffered is not willed by God as an end in itself. For didn’t God in this case will death precisely as an end in itself? After all, there does not seem to be in the case of Ananias and Sapphira (as there is in the case of the lion and the lamb) some other natural substance that flourished, and thus attained its own good, by way of causing their deaths.
I would answer, however, that there was a larger good for the sake of which God willed this particular case of evil suffered. Ananias and Sapphira were, after all, being punished by God for a grave sin. And punishment, as I argued in a post from not too long ago, is a good thing. It is the correction of a disorder, a restoration of the natural connection between evildoing on the one hand and the suffering of a harm on the other. God willed the evil suffered by Ananias and Sapphira as part of this larger good of securing retributive justice, as well, perhaps, as part of the realization of one of the secondary ends of punishment (deterrence).
To be sure, the case is unlike the lion and lamb example insofar as it does not involve a substance flourishing or realizing its good by way of the bad suffered by some other thing. All the same, punishment is a good which of its nature necessarily involves the suffering of an evil as a concomitant – namely the harm inflicted on the evildoer, which remains a harm even though it is deserved. So, the case does fit Davies’ overall account of evil suffered.
(For more on the nature of punishment, see By Man Shall His Blood Be Shed: A Catholic Defense of Capital Punishment . For more on the nature of divine action and the problem of evil, see the forthcoming Five Proofs of the Existence of God .)
Published on May 11, 2017 18:13
May 1, 2017
Caught in the web

Philosopher and AI critic Hubert Dreyfus has died. John Schwenkler on Dreyfus at First Things.
A new article from David Oderberg: “Co-operation in the Age of Hobby Lobby: When Sincerity is Not Enough,” in the current issue of Expositions . (Follow the link and click on the PDF.)
Philosopher Daniel Bonevac on being a conservative in academia, at Times Higher Education.At Aeon, Adam Frank argues that materialism cannot explain consciousness.
At Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, a review of Fran O’Rourke’s book Aristotelian Interpretations .
Philosopher Anthony McCarthy on Peter Singer and sexual consent, at Public Discourse.
The Albertus Magnus Center for Scholastic Studies announces its Summer Program for 2017.
Business Insider reveals the fantastic story behind the Marvel movie no one was ever supposed to see.
Roger Scruton on existentialism, at the Claremont Review of Books. Scruton profiled at The New Criterion.
At The Catholic Thing, Prof. Eduardo Echeverria on Pope Benedict’s and Pope Francis’s contrasting views on Gospel and Law. At First Things, historian Bronwen Catherine McShea on Pope Francis as historian.
Politico on how Pat Buchanan paved the way for Donald Trump.
Reason on Hayek’s Road to Serfdom and the situation in Venezuela.
The New Yorker profiles Daniel Dennett.
National Review on Bill Nye the Left-Wing Hack Guy. Even the New Republic thinks he’s become an embarrassment.
At First Things, Stephen Barr reviews Robert Berwick and Noam Chomsky’s new book on language and evolution.
The Chronicle of Higher Education on the Claremont conservatives and Trump.
Peter Adamson on medieval Jewish, Christian, and Islamic philosophy, at Aeon.
Also at Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, a review of Nancy Cartwright and Keith Ward’s new anthology Rethinking Order after the Laws of Nature .
Jerry Coyne advises his fellow left-wingers to stop demonizing Trump supporters. Noam Chomsky mocks Democrats for their obsession with Russia. Andrew Sullivan wonders why Democrats feel sorry for Hillary Clinton.
Aeon on the 25th anniversary of Francis Fukuyama’s The End of History and the Last Man.
Marvel Comics finds that political correctness isn’t selling. The Federalist comments. Marvel has had to fire an artist for inserting hidden Islamist messages into an X-Men comic book.
At the Times Literary Supplement, Steven Nadler asks: Exactly when did modern philosophy get started?
Reason and tolerance = shouting mindless slogans! Quillette on the tyranny of flash mobs. At City Journal, Heather Mac Donald on her ordeal at Claremont McKenna. Slate on the creepy so-called “March for Science.” Some left-wingers defend Ann Coulter’s right to speak.
Vintage Geek on common misconceptions about pulp-era science fiction.
Published on May 01, 2017 19:24
April 26, 2017
Five Proofs preview

The arguments in question are what I call the Aristotelian proof, the Neo-Platonic proof, the Augustinian proof, the Thomistic proof, and the Rationalist proof. As those labels indicate, each of the arguments has a long history in the tradition. They can be found in some form or other in thinkers like Aristotle, Plotinus, Augustine, Aquinas, and Leibniz. However, the specific formulations are my own. I am not presenting the arguments exactly as any of these thinkers presented them, and I am not doing exegesis of any of their works.
That is deliberate. In Aquinas and in The Last Superstition , I treat the question of God’s existence by way of expounding and defending Aquinas’s own arguments. That was appropriate given the specific aims of those books, but it has a downside. As readers of those books know, properly to understand Aquinas’s Five Ways, you first have to understand all the background philosophical theses he presupposes in the arguments but actually develops and defends elsewhere. For example, you need to understand his account of what change is, of how efficient causation works and the different kinds of causal series that there are, of the structure of a material substance, and so on. You also need to disentangle these background philosophical theses from the dated and mistaken scientific claims Aquinas sometimes used to illustrate them, but which are not in fact essential to them. That is why, in both books, the reader has to work through seventy pages or so of fairly abstract general metaphysics before getting to the specific topic of what Aquinas had to say about God’s existence.
In the years since writing Aquinas, I became convinced that there was a need for a book that approaches things differently. In particular, there was a need for a book that just gets straight to the main thrust of each of the best arguments for God’s existence, introducing the relevant background metaphysical notions along the way rather than in a separate prolegomenon, and without getting bogged down in exegetical questions or being limited to discussing what some particular writer of the past had to say. That’s what Five Proofs does. I defend an Aristotelian proof, but not Aristotle’sown formulation exactly; a Neo-Platonicproof, but without doing any exegesis of Plotinus’s Enneads; and so on.
The Aristotelian proof, as you might expect, is an argument from the distinction between actuality and potentiality to the existence of a purely actual actualizer of the existence of things. The Neo-Platonic proof is an argument from the existence of things that are composite to a first cause that is absolutely simple or non-composite. The Augustinian proof is an argument from realism about universals, propositions, possible worlds, and purported abstract objects in general to the existence of an infinite divine intellect in which these entities must reside. The Thomistic proof is an argument from the existence of things whose essence is distinct from their existence to a first cause which is subsistent existence itself. The Rationalist proof is an argument to the existence of an absolutely necessary being from the principle of sufficient reason, where the latter is interpreted in Scholastic rather than Leibnizian terms. Each of these arguments is developed and defended at much greater length than I have treated any of them elsewhere.
Each of the first five chapters of the book is devoted to one of these arguments, and the structure of each of these chapters is as follows. First, I argue in a discursive or informal way for the existence of something fitting a certain key description – being a purely actual actualizer, or an absolutely simple or non-composite cause, or what have you. Second, I argue in a discursive or informal way that anything fitting this key description must also possess the key divine attributes – unity, immutability, immateriality, omnipotence, omniscience, and so forth. Third, I then recapitulate the argumentation of the first two sections in a more formal way, showing how the reasoning can be set out carefully in a long step-by-step demonstration that lays bare its basic logical structure. Fourth, I address all the main objections that have been or might be raised against the argument. Again, I follow this procedure for each of the arguments in these first five chapters.
In the sixth chapter of the book, which is quite long – almost a short book by itself – I treat in much more detail all of the key divine attributes, as well as God’s relationship to the world. In particular, I argue at length for God’s unity, simplicity, immutability, immateriality, incorporeality, eternity, necessity, omnipotence, omniscience, perfect goodness, will, love, and incomprehensibility. I also defend the doctrines of divine conservation and concurrence. These issues will all have been dealt with to some extent in the earlier chapters, but the sixth chapter is intended to probe them at greater depth, to address all the main objections, and so on.
The seventh and final chapter of the book is an “omnibus” treatment of all the main objections to arguments for God’s existence of the sort defended in the book. Once again, these matters will have been dealt with to some extent in the earlier chapters, but the aim of the seventh chapter is to probe them at much greater depth, and also to deal with objections that aren’t treated in the earlier chapters.
The book is, then, a general work of natural theology, as concerned with the divine nature as it is with God’s existence. Naturally, it is written from the point of view of a Thomist, but it also interacts critically and in some detail with the literature in contemporary analytic philosophy of religion, both theist and atheist. Essentially it does for natural theology what my book Scholastic Metaphysics did for that subject.
More information to come…
Published on April 26, 2017 19:30
April 19, 2017
Empirical science and the transcendentals

Even simplicity stripped of its aesthetic dimension remains problematic. Ladyman brings it up in the context of discussing methodological principles in science that appear to be unfalsifiable (contra Popper’s famous criterion of what demarcates science from non-science). Paul Feyerabend argues that the scientific obsession with unifying phenomena by bringing them under simple general laws often involves an oversimplification that papers over the “abundance” and diversity that actually exists in nature.
There is some truth in these criticisms (and, in my view, in Feyerabend’s in particular). Still, there is also something plausible in the scientist’s concern for simplicity and beauty, which is why scientists persist in valuing these criteria despite the fact that they are indeed problematic, or at least are problematic giventhe philosophical assumptions to which scientists tend either explicitly or implicitly to be committed.
But the problem, I would say, is precisely with those background philosophical assumptions – namely, modern post-Cartesian, post-Humean assumptions – rather than with the criteria of simplicity and beauty themselves. For these criteria are not only not problematic, but on the contrary are quite natural, given a more traditional metaphysics – in particular, given the Scholastic doctrine of the transcendentals, which has its roots in Platonic and Aristotelian philosophy.
A “transcendental” property, in the sense in question here, is one that all being or reality as such possesses simply by virtue of being, and which can accordingly be predicated of everything. The standard list includes (in addition to being itself), oneness (or unity), goodness, and truth. Some writers regard beauty as an additional transcendental, though others take it to be just a special case of goodness. Either way, it is among the properties we can predicate of all being.
The transcendentals are “convertible” in the sense that they are really all the same thing looked at from different points of view. For example, truth is being considered as an object of the intellect, and goodness is being considered as an object of the will. Because they are convertible, wherever we can apply one transcendental, we can apply the others. Hence if we can say of a thing that it has being, then we can also say of it that it is good, that it is one, that it is true, and that it has beauty.
To take a simple example, consider a cat. To be a cat at all is to be a good cat in the sense of a good specimen of “catness”; and to be deficient as a specimen is, by the same token, to have less being. For instance, if a cat is missing a leg, it lacks some of the being or reality that is constitutive of “catness,” and is for that reason less good a specimen of “catness” than a cat with all four legs would be. And a byproduct of that imperfection is an absence of some of the beautythat would be present in a more perfect specimen. To be a cat is also to exhibit oneness or unity insofar as in a fully functioning cat, all its parts operate together for the sake of the whole. When this is not the case – when there is some dysfunction that prevents the parts from so operating – the cat is once again lackingsome of the being or reality that is constitutive of “catness,” and it is also once again lacking some of the goodness and beauty it would otherwise have. To be a cat is also to be a true cat in the sense of being something conforming to the concept that an intellect would form of what it is to be a cat. In these ways the being of a cat is convertible with its unity, goodness, beauty, and truth.
Needless to say, fully to spell out the doctrine of the transcendentals, and to justify the more general Scholastic metaphysical background assumptions needed in order to make it intelligible, would take more than a brief blog post. I give an exposition and defense of the doctrine in Aquinas (see especially pp. 31-36) and in my essay “Being, the Good, and the Guise of the Good,” reprinted in Neo-Scholastic Essays .
The point for present purposes is just this. Given the transcendentals, it is not surprising that considerations of simplicity and beauty would be thought appropriate criteria for choosing between theories about objective reality. Note first that the transcendentals being and truth are relatively unproblematic even given standard modern metaphysical assumptions. (Though I wouldn’t say that they are unproblematic full stop. See the remarks about truth below.) No one thinks it contrary to the objectivity of science when scientists say that the entities their theories postulate have being or reality, or that the theories themselves are true. (To be sure, instrumentalists deny that the entities referred to by scientific theories really exist and that the theories are strictly true. But instrumentalists don’t accuse scientific realists of a failure of objectivity, but merely of being mistaken.)
Now, given the convertibility of the transcendentals, wherever there is being or truth, there is also going to be oneness or unity and (either because it is a transcendental in its own right or because it follows from goodness) beauty. Hence the absence of unity and beauty is bound to be an indicator of some absence of being and truth.
Consider also that “simplicity” of the kind taken to be a criterion of theory choice is closely related to the transcendental oneness or unity. Ultimate explanation in science is thought to involve taking all the diverse and complex natural phenomena and higher-level laws that there are down to one set of fundamental laws rather than to several, and to laws that can be stated relatively crisply and elegantly rather than in a convoluted way. This bears a family resemblance to the Scholastic notion that there is a hierarchy of kinds of thing ordered according to their degrees of simplicity and unity. On this view, aggregates have a lower degree of unity or oneness than substances do, material substances have a lower degree of unity than incorporeal substances (i.e. angels) do, and incorporeal substances have a lower degree of unity than God, who is absolutely simple or non-composite. And this hierarchy of degrees of unity is also a hierarchy of degrees of being and of goodness (and thus of beauty).
Aquinas’s Fourth Way essentially makes of this notion of a hierarchy of things possessing the transcendental attributes an argument for the existence of God. The basic idea is that degrees of being, goodness, oneness, etc. point to the existence of something that is the most real, unified, good, etc. thing possible – where the most real thing, the most unified thing, etc. must be the same one thing looked at from different points of view, given the convertibility of the transcendentals. (See Aquinas for a detailed exposition of the argument.)
Modern scientists don’t reason exactly this way, of course, but they aren’t as far from the spirit of the argument as they might seem at first glance. For they do tend to think that the more ultimate or fundamental some set of laws is, the more simple and beautiful they will be. There is even a sense in which they take the fundamental laws to be more realthan anything else. For one thing, they take these fundamental laws to be in some sense the source of the reality of all other things. For another, they constantly feel a pressure in the direction of a reductionismwhich treats the fundamental laws and the entities they govern (fundamental particles, say) as the most real entities. To be sure, they often resist this pressure – by no means are all scientists ontological reductionists – but the point is that the fundamental laws and entities tend to be treated as the only unproblematically real things, whereas everything else has to either reduced to, or explained as emerging out of, these fundamental laws and entities. What is fundamental is in that sense taken to have the highest degree of being as well as the highest degree of simplicity and beauty.
That is not far from the thrust of Fourth Way-style reasoning. One difference, of course, is that modern scientists don’t take the reasoning to what Aquinas would regard as its logical conclusion, viz. that the ultimateexplanatory principle would have to be something entirely beyond the corporeal world altogether (not to mention something that would have to have the divine attributes). A second difference is that modern scientists are not really systematic about all this. They retain their attachment to criteria like simplicity and beauty in a merely intuitive way, without bothering clearly to explain what their rational basis is. (These two differences are connected. For to work out rationally and systematically what in modern science are left as mere intuitions would lead precisely to a return to something like the doctrine of the transcendentals – and to its theological implications as the sequel.)
As indicated above, even the transcendental truthis, on closer inspection, problematic when detached from the older metaphysics. Michael Polanyi points out in his book Personal Knowledge that simplicity as a criterion of theory choice essentially functions as a proxy for rationality. That is to say, scientists are drawn to theories that make the world intelligible. But a thing’s rationality and intelligibility have to do with its relation to the mind, and modern scientists tend to be committed to the idea that an “objective” account of the world must subtract from it any reference to the mind. Hence scientists operate with what amount in Polanyi’s view to “a set of euphemisms” (p. 16). He writes:
The term ‘simplicity’ functions then merely as a disguise for another meaning than its own. It is used for smuggling an essential quality into our appreciation of a scientific theory, which a mistaken conception of objectivity forbids us openly to acknowledge.
What has just been said of ‘simplicity’ applies equally to ‘symmetry’ and ‘economy’… They must stand for those peculiar intellectual harmonies which reveal, more profoundly and permanently than any sense-experience, the presence of objective truth.
I shall call this practice a pseudo-substitution. It is used to play down man’s real and indispensable intellectual powers for the sake of maintaining an ‘objectivist’ framework which in fact cannot account for them. (pp. 16-17)
Though he doesn’t put it this way, what Polanyi is pointing out here is that modern scientists are implicitly committed to the reality of truth as truth is understood within the doctrine of the transcendentals – that is to say, to truth conceived of as being or reality in its relation to an intellect. The reason they prefer terms like “simplicity” and “economy” is that they tend also to be committed to the assumption that intellect is a highly derivative phenomenon – a mere byproduct of evolutionary history that appears very late in the game as it were – and thus ought not to enter into our characterization of reality at the most fundamental level. And the trouble is that when this reference to the intellect is deleted, it is no longer clear why simplicity and the like ought to be criteria of theory choice.
Keats was right to say that “beauty is truth, truth beauty,” but wrong to follow up this claim with the further assertion that “that is all ye know on earth, and all ye need to know.” For we do need to know something else – namely the traditional, Scholastic metaphysics that makes the first claim intelligible.
Published on April 19, 2017 17:14
April 9, 2017
The problem of Hume’s problem of induction

But there is, Hume argues, no such connection. For it is at least conceivable that bread could fail to nourish us, in a way it is not conceivable that a bachelor could be married. In general, it is conceivable with respect to any cause that its usual effect might fail to follow upon it. Hence we cannot reason on the basis of the relations of ideas to the conclusion that causes that we have not observed will operate like those we have observed.
The other way induction might purportedly be justified would be in terms of “matters of fact.” The proposition that many bachelors go to singles bars is true, not because the idea of being a bachelor logically entails the idea of going to a singles bar, but rather because it simply happens to be a contingent empirical fact that many bachelors do this. To justify induction in terms of “matters of fact” would involve arguing that as a matter of contingent empirical fact, induction has been a reliable way of reasoning, so that we have grounds to trust it in the future.
But the trouble with this attempt to justify induction is that it is circular. To infer from the fact that many observed bachelors have gone to singles bars the conclusion that many unobserved bachelors will do so too presupposes the reliability of induction. To infer from the fact that induction has been reliable in observed cases the conclusion that it will be reliable in future cases also presupposes the reliability of induction – where its reliability is, in this case, exactly what such an argument is supposed to be showing.
In summary, Hume’s argument against the possibility of justifying induction goes as follows:
1. Induction could be rationally justified only in terms of either the relations of ideas or matters of fact.
2. But it cannot be justified in terms of the relations of ideas, since for any cause and any effect it is conceivable that the one could in the future exist without the other.
3. And it cannot be justified in terms of matters of fact, since such a purported justification would presuppose the reliability of induction and thus beg the question.
4. So induction cannot be rationally justified.
As David Stove once said of Plato’s Theory of Forms, the sequel to Hume’s argument has been centuries of rapturous applause among philosophers. Stove didn’t mean it as a compliment; he was mocking something he took to be overrated. The mockery is in my view not justified in Plato’s case, but it would have been justified had the barb been directed instead at Hume’s overrated argument. For what we have here is one of many instances of Hume’s application of general philosophical presuppositions which we know to be highly problematic at best and demonstrably false at worst.
First, the initial premise of Hume’s argument is an application of Hume’s Fork, the principle that all knowable propositions concern either relations of ideas or matters of fact. But Hume’s Fork – which is itself neither true by virtue of the relations of its constituent ideas, nor true by virtue of empirically ascertainable facts – is notoriously self-refuting. It is as metaphysical a principle as any Hume was trying to undermine with it, and its very promulgation presupposes that there is a third epistemic point of view additional to the two Hume was willing to recognize. In that case, though, Hume’s celebrated “problem of induction” cannot even get out of the starting gate. Its entire force depends on a dichotomy that is demonstrably false.
Nor can the Humean plausibly salvage the argument by softening Hume’s Fork so as to avoid the self-refutation problem. For the softening can take one of three forms. The Humean could liberalize the principle by admitting that there is after all a third category in addition to “relations of ideas” and “matters of fact”; or he could maintain this dichotomy while liberalizing the notion of “relations of ideas” in such a way that Hume’s Fork itself will come out true by virtue of the relations of ideas; or he could maintain the dichotomy while liberalizing the notion of “matters of fact” in such a way that Hume’s Fork will come out true by virtue of matters of fact.
Whether and how any of these strategies could be developed in a plausible way is another question. But the point for present purposes is that, however that might go, if he is going to salvage Hume’s problem of induction, the Humean will have to soften Hume’s Fork in such a way that it will vindicate Hume’ Fork itself without also vindicating induction at the same time. In particular, the Humean will have to acknowledge a third category of knowable propositions in addition to relations of ideas and matters of fact while at the same time showing that induction isn’t justifiable in terms of this third category. Or he will have to liberalize the notion of “relations of ideas” while at the same time showing that induction isn’t justifiable in terms of this new, liberalized notion. Or he will have to liberalize the notion of matters of fact while at the same time showing that induction isn’t justifiable in terms of thatnew, liberalized notion.
Good luck with all that. Until one of these strategies is actually developed, we don’t really have a Humean “problem of induction.”
That’s just one problem. Another is that Hume’s second premise depends on the principle that conceivability is a guide to real possibility. Now, contemporary philosophers never tire of pointing out how problematic this principle is when Cartesians deploy it in arguments for their brand of dualism. The Cartesian says that we can clearly conceive, without contradiction, of minds existing in the absence of bodies, and concludes from this that it is therefore possible in principle for minds to exist apart from bodies. But how, the critic responds, can we rule out the possibility that this seems conceivable only because of a deficiency in our grasp of the mind? Someone with only a vague understanding of what a Euclidean triangle is might think it possible for such a triangle to have angles that add up to something other than 180 degrees. When he acquires a better grasp he will realize that this is not in fact possible. Perhaps, the critic suggests, a more penetrating grasp of the nature of the mind would reveal that it cannot really exist apart from matter.
But the same sort of objection can be raised against Hume (and, in my view, with greater justice). Perhaps if we had a complete grasp of the nature of bread and the nature of the human body, we would see that it is not in fact possible for bread to fail to be nourishing to us. If so, then we would be justified in judging that bread will nourish us in the future just as it has in the past.
Now, the reason Hume is so confident that this is not the case is because of what commentators call his copy principle, viz. the thesis that an idea is just a faint copy of an impression. I have an impressionof red when I am looking at a certain apple. When the apple is not present I can call to mind what that color looked like, and this mental image is (Hume claims) my idea of red. More complex ideas are made up of combinations of simpler ones of this sort. My idea of bread, for example, is just a combination of the idea of a certain color, the idea of a certain shape, the idea of a certain texture, and so forth. Thus understood, it seems plausible to say that there is nothing in my idea of bread that entails that it will be nourishing in all cases.
But this account of our ideas is ludicrous. It reflects the imagist thesis that a concept is essentially a kind of mental image, and imagism is demonstrably false. We have a great many concepts that are clearly not identifiable with mental images. For example, the concept of triangularity is not identifiable with any mental image. Any triangle you can imagine will always be of a certain specific color – black, red, green, or whatever – whereas the concept triangularityapplies to all triangles whatever their color. Any triangle you can imagine will be a right triangle, or an equilateral triangle, or in some other way have features that don’t apply to all triangles, whereas the concept triangularity does apply to all triangles. And so forth. This is just the beginning of the problems with imagism. (Here’s a fun exercise: Try to identify the mental image that the concept mental imagemight be identified with.)
Then there is the assumption that all necessity is logicalnecessity, viz. the sort of necessity exhibited by the relations between concepts. Aristotelians and other non-Humean philosophers would deny this. They hold that there is a deeper, metaphysical kind of necessity that exists in things themselves and not merely in our concepts of things. Logical necessity, on this view, is an echo of this deeper sort of necessity. And the echo might not ring out very strongly in a mind that has too superficial an acquaintance with all the relevant facts. Hence, suppose that, given the nature of bread and given the nature of a healthy human body, it cannot possibly be the case that bread will fail to nourish such a body. It may still turn out that a given person might conceive of a scenario wherein bread fails to be nourishing, not because such a failure is really possible, but rather merely because that person’s intellect has not attained a sufficiently penetrating grasp of the natures of bread and of the body.
For the non-Humean, then, it is simply not the case that all propositions are either necessary but mere conceptual truths (“relations of ideas”), or empirical but merely contingent truths (“matters of fact”). There are also truths which are empirical but nevertheless necessary. That bread will nourish the body could be a necessary truth even if we can know that it is true (if it is in fact true) only by empirical investigation of the natures of bread and of the body.
Naturally, the Humean will disagree with all of this, but the point is that, unless he offers an independent argument against these alternative ways of understanding the nature of concepts, necessary truth, etc., he will not have given us any non-question-begging reason to believe that there is a “problem of induction.”
The real problem, then, is not the problem of justifying induction. The real problem is justifying the claim that there is a “problem of induction” that remains once we have put aside the false or otherwise problematic philosophical assumptions that Hume himself deployed when arguing that induction cannot be justified.
Published on April 09, 2017 15:36
Edward Feser's Blog
- Edward Feser's profile
- 325 followers
Edward Feser isn't a Goodreads Author
(yet),
but they
do have a blog,
so here are some recent posts imported from
their feed.
