Edward Feser's Blog, page 64
August 8, 2017
Capital punishment with Patrick Coffin

Published on August 08, 2017 13:53
August 7, 2017
Capital punishment with Prager (UPDATED)

Tomorrow, Tuesday, August 8 at 11 am PT, Joe Bessette and I will be on The Dennis Prager Show to discuss our book By Man Shall His Blood Be Shed: A Catholic Defense of Capital Punishment . For other recent radio and television interviews about the book, follow the relevant links here.
Published on August 07, 2017 08:43
Capital punishment with Prager

Published on August 07, 2017 08:43
August 4, 2017
Capital punishment on EWTN

Links to other recent interviews can be found here, here, and here.
Published on August 04, 2017 18:48
July 29, 2017
Cartesian angelism

The position of angels in the hierarchy of reality illuminates the similarities and differences between the kinds of things which exist (or, if you don’t believe in angels, which could exist). At the bottom of the hierarchy come inanimate material things – rocks, dirt, water, and so forth. Next come the vegetative forms of life, which take in nutrients, grow, and reproduce themselves but do nothing beyond this. Then we have sensory or animal forms of life, which carry out the vegetative functions but add to them sensation, appetite, and locomotion or self-movement. Above mere animals are rational animals or human beings. Human beings do everything other animals do, but on top of that possess intellect and will; and for Aquinas and other Scholastic thinkers, these are incorporeal activities. A human being is, accordingly, the kind of substance which possesses at the same time both bodily and non-bodily attributes.
Now, there is, as it were, metaphysical room in between human beings and God for a further kind of thing – something which is entirelyincorporeal rather than being merely partially incorporeal (as human beings are), but which is nevertheless finite and in need of being created (as God is not). That is what an angel is.
On Aquinas’s analysis, among the things we can say about angels are the following:
1. Being utterly incorporeal by nature, angels lack sense organs or brain activity. They do not have sensory experiences, or the mental imagery that follows upon these. Hence their mode of knowledge is not like ours. We come to know things through the senses, and form concepts by abstracting them from the things we experience. An angel, by contrast, has all its concepts and knowledge “built in” at its creation. In other words, it possesses innate ideas.
2. Angels are not in time, though they are not strictly eternal either. What is in time, as corporeal things are, is changeable both in its substance and in its accidents. What is strictly eternal, as God is, is utterly unchangeable. Angels are unchangeable in their substance, since they are incorporeal. An angel is not composed of matter which might lose its substantial form and thereby go out of existence. It is in this way incorruptible or immortal. But it can change in its accidents insofar as it can choose either this or that. This middle ground between time and eternity is what Aquinas calls “aeviternity.”
3. For these reasons, an angel does not know things in a discursive way. It does not have to engage in processes like reasoning from premises to a conclusion, weighing alternative hypotheses, or otherwise “figuring things out” the way we do. It simply knows what it knows “all at once,” as it were.
4. Unlike the human soul, an angel is not the form of any body. A human being, again, is the kind of substance which possesses both corporeal and incorporeal activities. It accordingly has the substantial form of the kind of thing capable of both activities. When its corporeal side is destroyed, the substance itself is not thereby destroyed, because it was never entirely corporeal in the first place. That is why the human soul carries on beyond death – qua substantial form, it continues to inform the now incomplete substance of which it is the form, a substance reduced to its incorporeal operations. But this is not its natural state. In the absence of matter, the substance in question cannot do all the things it is naturally inclined to do (seeing, hearing, walking, talking, etc.). But angels are not like that. Being incorporeal is their natural state.
5. All angels fall under the same genus (which is why they are all angels), but there cannot be more than one member of any angelic species. The reason is that, for Aquinas, matter is what distinguishes one member of a species of thing from another. Hence, since angels are completely incorporeal, there is no way in principle by which one member of an angelic species could be distinguished from another. If there are two or more angels, then, there are ipso facto two or more angelic species. The way these species differ is the only way they can differ in purely intellectual substances, viz. degree of intellectual power.
See (among other works) Summa Theologiae I.50-64 for more details. But this much gives us enough to understand why, from an Aristotelian-Thomistic point of view, the Cartesian view of human nature is deeply mistaken. To be sure, like the Cartesian, the Aristotelian-Thomistic philosopher regards the human intellect as incorporeal. But that does not suffice to make for a purely incorporeal substance. Rather, a human being is a substance which of its nature possesses both corporeal and incorporeal operations.
A Cartesian res cogitans, by contrast, is a thing that thinks and nothing more than that. That is why the Cartesian (unlike the Aristotelian-Thomistic philosopher) is a substance dualist. The res cogitans is an utterly incorporeal substance but nevertheless a complete one. The body must accordingly be a second, distinct complete substance. From an Aristotelian-Thomistic point of view, this entails that with Descartes’ res cogitans, we are no longer talking about a human intellect at all. We are really implicitly talking about an angelicintellect. (This was not Descartes’ own intention, to be sure. The point, though, is that that is what his position entails, whether he welcomes it or not.)
As I noted in another post not too long ago, the famous mind-body interaction problem facing the Cartesian ultimately is not, from the Aristotelian-Thomistic point of view, the problem of explaining how an incorporeal substance can be the efficient cause of a bodily event. After all, God causes the physical world to exist, and angels can cause various events in the natural world to occur, and these cases do not raise any special problem about causation. (Or at least, Aristotelian-Thomistic philosophers don’t think these cases any more problematic than Cartesians do.)
The problem facing the Cartesian is rather how to explain mind-body interaction in a way that doesn’t reduce it to something comparable to demonic possession. A fallen angel moves a bit of matter around in something like the way a poltergeist is popularly thought to move material things around. A Cartesian res cogitans controlling a res extensa is essentially like a demon’s control of one of the Gadarene swine – the manipulation of something utterly extrinsic to the manipulator, to which it is only contingently related. That is a bizarre model of human nature that is not compatible with the intimate way we are actually related to our own bodies, which is why Gilbert Ryle famously characterized the Cartesian view as the theory of the “ghost in the machine.”
The fact that Descartes attributes innate ideas to us only underlines the extent to which his model of human nature is essentially an angelic model. And if Aquinas’s analysis of the angelic nature is correct, it entails further arguments against the Cartesian view of human nature. If the Cartesian view were correct, then (since it entails that the human intellect is essentially angel-like), it would follow that human knowledge would be “all at once” rather than discursive, that human intellects would not exist in time, and that each human being would be the unique member of his own species. But none of these things is true. Hence the Cartesian view of human nature is not correct.
Of course, Cartesians do not in fact attribute all of these features to a res cogitans, which is why it is not a perfect model for what an angelic intellect is like. The Cartesian does not see the implications of severing the human intellect from the body as thoroughly as Descartes severs it. Strictly speaking, the proper procedure is not to try to understand angels in terms of res cogitans, but rather to understand the notion of res cogitans – including the implicit aspects that Cartesians do not see – in light of the Thomistic analysis of angelic intellects.
[For more on the Aristotelian-Thomistic account of human nature, enter soul, dualism, mind-body, and related terms in the search bar of this blog]
Published on July 29, 2017 11:14
July 26, 2017
Capital punishment on radio and TV

My recent Catholic Answers Focus appearance is available online. So is my appearance on The Live Hour with Todd Sylvester . Links to other recent radio interviews can be found hereand here. Stay tuned for announcements of future appearances.
Published on July 26, 2017 22:39
July 20, 2017
Msgr. Swetland’s confusions

Msgr. Swetland versus Catholic doctrine on scripture
Msgr. Swetland tells us that while the Church historically has taught that capital punishment can in principle be legitimate, she is nevertheless “coming to recognize it as intrinsically evil.” He acknowledges that the Church has not gone so far as explicitly to teach this, but he thinks that she could do so in the future, and evidently this is a change he would welcome. For the thesis that capital punishment is an “intrinsic evil” is, he says, a “theological speculation” which he personally favors. In the monsignor’s opinion, “it’s always wrong to choose death – God never chooses death.”
That “God never chooses death” would be a surprise to Ananias and Sapphira, Korah, the firstborn of Egypt, and countless others who are described in scripture as having been slain by God. But putting that aside, capital punishment is certainly sanctioned throughout scripture, as we document at length in the book. Judging from an essay Msgr. Swetland contributed to a volume on Catholicism and capital punishment, he has been influenced in his thinking on this subject by “new natural law” theorist and death penalty opponent E. Christian Brugger (whose book on capital punishment Joe and I respond to at length in our own book). But even Brugger acknowledges that capital punishment is sanctioned throughout scripture. For example, Brugger admits that existing attempts to reinterpret Genesis 9:6 (the verse quoted in the title of our book) are not convincing, and that the passage remains a “problem” for views like his own.
Now, as Joe and I also note in the book, it is the de fide teaching of the Catholic Church that scripture cannot teach error where matters of faith and morals are concerned. Note that we are not saying that scripture teaches error on other matters. The point is that, whatever one says about that issue, that scripture is inerrant at least on matters of faith and morals is undeniably a doctrine of the Church. The Church also lays down clear criteria concerning how scripture can be interpreted. Hence, the First Vatican Council says:
These books the Church holds to be sacred and canonical not because she subsequently approved them by her authority after they had been composed by unaided human skill, nor simply because they contain revelation without error, but because, being written under the inspiration of the Holy Spirit, they have God as their author…
[I]n matters of faith and morals , belonging as they do to the establishing of Christian doctrine, that meaning of Holy Scripture must be held to be the true one, which Holy mother Church held and holds, since it is her right to judge of the true meaning and interpretation of Holy Scripture.
In consequence, it is not permissible for anyone to interpret Holy Scripture in a sense contrary to this, or indeed against the unanimous consent of the fathers .
End quote. Now, the Church has always held, and still holds, that the legitimacy in principle of capital punishment is taught in scripture. And as even Brugger admits, there was a “consensus” among the Fathers of the Church that the legitimacy in principle of capital punishment is taught by scripture. This shows, all by itself, that to say that capital punishment is “intrinsically evil” is manifestly irreconcilable with Catholic orthodoxy. For if scripture cannot teach moral error and the consensus of the Fathers on what scripture says also cannot be in error, and the Fathers hold that scripture teaches that capital punishment is not intrinsically evil, then capital punishment is not intrinsically evil, and that’s that.
Msgr. Swetland’s “theological speculation” that capital punishment is intrinsically evil is, accordingly, simply heterodox. He has no right as a Catholic theologian to entertain it or to teach others that it is within the range of legitimate theological opinion. In 1976, under Pope Paul VI, a Vatican commission on capital punishment stated:
That the state has the right to enforce the death penalty has been ceded by the church for centuries… The Church has never condemned its use by the state… The Church has condemned the denial of that right.
In stating this, the commission was echoing the solemn teaching of previous popes like Innocent III, who required that the Waldensian heretics affirm the state’s right in principle to resort to capital punishment as a condition of their reconciliation with the Church. (The relevant texts can all be found in our book.)
As these remarks indicate, and as Joe and I demonstrate in the book, there are several lines of argument that show that the judgment that capital punishment is “intrinsically evil” is heterodox. But the scriptural considerations are the ones that came up in the debate, so let’s focus on those.
During our debate, I repeatedly asked Msgr. Swetland if it was his opinion that scripture teaches moral error. And it is telling that Msgr. Swetland repeatedly failed to answer that question directly. He didn’t say “Yes, scripture teaches moral error” – and to do so would, of course, put him at odds with the First Vatican Council and with various papal statements on the inerrancy of scripture – but, interestingly, neither did he say “No, scripture never teaches moral error.” What he repeatedly did instead was to try to dodge the question by changing the subject, in (by my count) four different ways. Let’s consider them one by one:
1. The “development of doctrine” canard: Msgr. Swetland claims that the thesis that capital punishment is intrinsically evil would be a “development” of past Catholic teaching. In fact, of course, it would not be a “development” at all, but an outright rejection and reversal of past teaching. Orthodox Catholic theorists of the “development of doctrine” – most famously, Cardinal John Henry Newman – are always careful to distinguish a true development from a reversal or corruption of doctrine. A development never contradicts what the Church has solemnly affirmed in the past. It simply makes explicit what was previously only implicit in the tradition. It may involve closing off certain theological options that had previously been left open to free discussion. But what it cannot do is to take some proposition that scripture and tradition have positively asserted and then go on to negate it. That would be to introduce a contradiction into the tradition, and thereby to falsify the Church’s claim to preserve intact the deposit of faith.
Msgr. Swetland repeatedly cited slavery as an example of something the Church previously approved of but later condemned, at the Second Vatican Council. He claims that for the Church to teach the intrinsic immorality of capital punishment would be to make a similar change. But as I tried to explain during our exchange, the monsignor grossly oversimplifies and misrepresents the history of Catholic teaching on slavery. What most people think of when they hear the word “slavery” is chattel slavery, which involves complete ownership of another person, the way one might own an animal or an inanimate object. This is indeed intrinsically gravely evil, and the Church condemns it. But the Church has always condemned it. It is not some novel or recent teaching.
There are, however, other practices that are sometimes loosely labeled “slavery” but which are very different from chattel slavery. For example, there is indentured servitude, which is a contract to give the right to one’s labor to another person for a prolonged period of time – for example, in payment of a debt. And there is penal servitude, which involves forcing someone to labor as part of a punishment for a crime. Catholic theologians have long regarded some of these practices as so morally hazardous, and in particular as posing a serious enough danger of degenerating into chattel slavery, that in practicethey ought not to be employed. But the Church has not condemned them as intrinsicallyimmoral the way chattel slavery is. Indentured servitude, after all, is essentially an extreme version of an ordinary labor contract, and penal servitude is an extension of the loss of liberty any justly punished prisoner is already subject to.
This is not to deny that some individual Catholics have in the past fallaciously blurred the differences between these different practices so as to try to justify what amounts to chattel slavery, or that in the past some Catholics have positively approved of institutions like indentured servitude and not merely allowed that they might be permissible in principle. But when the relevant distinctions are made, it is clear that it is simply not true to say that the example of slavery shows that the Church herself once regarded as legitimate something she later condemned as intrinsically immoral. What she now regards as intrinsically immoral (chattel slavery) she always regarded as intrinsically immoral. What she has historically held is not intrinsically immoral (indentured servitude and penal servitude) she still has not condemned as intrinsically immoral. There simply has been no change of the sort Msgr. Swetland claims there has been, and which his argument requires there to have been.
The monsignor alleges that Gaudium et Spes 27 conflicts with my position, but it does no such thing. The passage is a general condemnation of practices that conflict with human dignity, and it gives a long list of examples, including not only slavery but also “deportation,” “attempts to coerce the will,” and “disgraceful working conditions.” What it does not do is to define any of these terms precisely or to make clear which practices are intrinsically evil and which are evil only given certain circumstances. Is Gaudium et Spes teaching that it is always and intrinsically wrong to deport someone (including, for example, sending a dangerous criminal back to his home country to be prosecuted)? Is the document saying that it is wrong to threaten a child with punishment if he does not do his homework (since this in some sense coerces his will)? Is it claiming that it is wrong to employ people in treating sewage or cleaning toilets, in coal and salt mines, or other unpleasant or dangerous occupations?
No one claims that Gaudium et Spes teaches any of these things. Its passing references to deportation, coercion, working conditions, etc. don’t address every question that might arise about these topics, because the passage in question isn’t trying to do that in the first place. It is simply making a general statement about human dignity and providing some brief illustrations. But by the same token, its passing reference to slavery is not trying to address every question that might arise about indentured or penal servitude, the proper interpretation of biblical passages that refer to slavery, etc.
This account of the history of Catholic teaching vis-à-vis slavery is not, by the way, some eccentric view of my own. It is common among mainstream theologians faithful to the magisterium of the Church. Interested readers should get hold of Fr. Joel Panzer’s book The Popes and Slavery . Some useful articles can also be found online here, here, and here.
Writers who claim that the Church made some radical about-face on the subject of slavery tend to be “progressive” theologians who are keen to use the example to justify radical changes to Catholic teaching on other matters – especially sexual morality – and to portray the Church of the past in a negative light. Why the monsignor would have any truck with such people, I have no idea.
2. Ignoring the distinction between permitting and commanding: A second way Msgr. Swetland tried to dodge my question about whether he thinks scripture has taught moral error is by insinuating that scripture merely “permitted” capital punishment. Now, to “permit” something is of course not necessarily to approve of it. Suppose a prickly neighbor of yours keeps taking fruit from a tree in your front yard without asking you first. But suppose also that you can live without the fruit and want to remain on good terms with this person, so that while you’d prefer that he not do this, you let it slide. You are permitting him to take the fruit even though you do not approve of him doing so.
Now, if scripture were merely permitting capital punishment in this sense, then there would be no reversal of scriptural teaching if the Church were to condemn it as intrinsically evil. But as I pointed out to Msgr. Swetland, scripture goes far beyond merely permitting capital punishment. There are many scriptural passages which positively approve of or even command capital punishment. For example, the Mosaic Law commands capital punishment for various offenses as part of the everyday system of criminal justice in ancient Israel. To be sure, that does not entail that those commands have application today, any more than other parts of the Mosaic Law do. But it does entail that, if capital punishment is (as Msgr. Swetland thinks it is) “intrinsically evil,” then we have to say that God commanded the Israelites to carry out intrinsically gravely evil acts as part of everyday life in Israel. It would be like God, through Moses, commanding the Israelites to perform abortions with regularity. How can this supposition possibly be reconciled with the Church’s de fide teaching that scripture does not teach moral error?
Nor is positive approval of capital punishment (as opposed to mere permission) by any means limited to the Mosaic Law. It can also be found, for example, in Genesis 9:6 and Romans 13:1-4. (In the book, Joe and I address at length attempts by Catholic opponents of capital punishment to reinterpret these passages.)
3. Ignoring the difference between prudential judgments and judgments of principle: A third way the monsignor attempted to avoid directly answering my question was by asking me questions. For example, he asked me if I would approve of applying the “eye for an eye” principle by gouging an offender’s eye out.
My answer to him was that I would not approve of applying it in that way, but not because doing so would be intrinsically wrong. It would not be intrinsically wrong. Consider the monstrous Lawrence Singleton, who raped a fifteen-year-old girl and cut off her forearms with a hatchet. This poor woman has to spend every day of the rest of her life not only disabled, but reminded of everything he did to her. Now, did Singleton deserve to have his own arms cut off as punishment? Absolutely he did. However, I would disapprove of actually meting out such punishments, to Singleton or to anyone else. For the moral hazards of routinely inflicting such gruesome punishments are simply too great. But this is a prudential judgment about how to apply moral principle, not a judgment to the effect that such punishments are intrinsically wrong.
The point is that to disapprove of extreme punishments like the ones in question does not commit one to saying that scripture approves of what is intrinsically immoral. Hence, if the monsignor meant to insinuate that the “eye for an eye” principle is an instance of scripture teaching moral error – though again, he does not explicitly say that – the example would not in fact support his case.
4. The “fundamentalist” smear: The fourth way in which Msgr. Swetland attempted to dodge my question was by a hand-waving reference to “difficult passages in scripture” and the accusation that my own reading of the specific passages that conflict with his view about capital punishment is “bizarre,” “not very Catholic,” and “sounds very fundamentalist.”
The truth, of course, is that my reading of the relevant scriptural passages is simply the reading one finds in the Fathers and Doctors of the Church, in two millennia of papal teaching, and in two millennia of mainstream Catholic theology. No Catholic theologian with a reputation for orthodoxy found these passages remotely “difficult” until about forty years ago, when Germain Grisez and other “new natural lawyers” invented their novel doctrine that capital punishment is intrinsically evil, and decided to try to find some way to change Catholic teaching to conform it to their personal theory. To label myreading of the relevant passages “bizarre” and “not very Catholic” is, frankly, Orwellian.
As to the charge of “fundamentalism,” Msgr. Swetland never explains how Joe and I are guilty of that. Is he claiming that we simply dogmatically appeal to scriptural proof texts, without giving arguments for the correctness of our reading or engaging with alternative readings? As anyone who has actually read our book knows, that is precisely the opposite of the truth. In fact we engage the exegetical disputes at length. But then, the “fundamentalist” label is rarely intended as a serious tool of theological analysis. Its use is rhetorical, a smear by which “progressive” theologians attempt to shut down debate. Again, why Msgr. Swetland would think it a good idea to ape their tactics, I have no idea.
The irony is that it is Msgr. Swetland himself who is engaging in dogmatic proof-texting. In particular, he repeatedly cites a remark from Pope John Paul II, or a passage from the Catechism or from some other church document, as if it suffices to prove his case – completely ignoring the fact that the correct interpretation of these sources is itself precisely part of what is at issue between us. This question-begging procedure exhibits exactly the kind of dogmatic and simplistic thinking of which he accuses Joe and me.
Msgr. Swetland versus Pope Benedict XVI
Let us turn now to Msgr. Swetland’s other major error. He claims that, even if he is wrong about capital punishment being intrinsicallyevil, Catholics are nevertheless now obligatedto oppose it in practice. Says the monsignor:
For prudential reasons, the bishops in the United States have said no Catholic can, without disobeying the bishops, be supporting… the death penalty in the United States. So, while theoretically we can talk about this, practicallyCatholics in the United States are bound, I believe, under the power of the teaching authority of the bishops in the United States to oppose the death penalty on prudential reasons.
End quote. Now, there are several reasons why this cannot be correct, which Joe and I spell out in the book. But one consideration I raised in the radio debate with Msgr. Swetland is a 2004 statement from Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger, then Prefect of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith (that is to say, the chief doctrinal spokesman of the Church next to the pope), and later to become Pope Benedict XVI. Ratzinger wrote:
Not all moral issues have the same moral weight as abortion and euthanasia. For example, if a Catholic were to be at odds with the Holy Father on the application of capital punishment or on the decision to wage war, he would not for that reason be considered unworthy to present himself to receive Holy Communion. While the Church exhorts civil authorities to seek peace, not war, and to exercise discretion and mercy in imposing punishment on criminals, it may still be permissible to take up arms to repel an aggressor or to have recourse to capital punishment. There may be a legitimate diversity of opinion even among Catholics about waging war and applying the death penalty, but not however with regard to abortion and euthanasia.
End quote. Now, it could not be clearer that what Cardinal Ratzinger is saying here flatly contradicts what Msgr. Swetland alleges. The monsignor says that Catholics cannot be “at odds with” the pope on the subject of capital punishment. Cardinal Ratzinger says that they canbe. The monsignor says that there cannot be “a legitimate diversity of opinion” among Catholics about “applyingthe death penalty.” Cardinal Ratzinger says that there can be.
The way Msgr. Swetland tried to get around this problem during our exchange was by seriously misrepresenting what Cardinal Ratzinger said. He insinuated that what Ratzinger was saying was merely that “there is room for legitimate disagreement about the theoretical permissibility of the death penalty.” The monsignor alleges that “at least now we all have to oppose it in practice, even if we can speculate about it in theory.” In other words, Msgr. Swetland’s contention appears to be that what Cardinal Ratzinger was saying in 2004 was merely that Catholics can disagree about whether capital punishment is intrinsically evil, but that the Cardinal was not denying that Catholics have to oppose it in practice.
But there are several reasons why this cannot be what Cardinal Ratzinger meant. Indeed, the monsignor’s reading is, frankly, absurd.
First, Ratzinger explicitly says that a Catholic may be “at odds with the Holy Father on the application of capital punishment,” that “it may still be permissible… to have recourse to capital punishment,” and that “there may be a legitimate diversity of opinion even among Catholics about… applying the death penalty.” He is talking precisely about practice, not theory.
Second, Msgr. Swetland’s interpretation cannot possibly make sense of Ratzinger’s statement that a Catholic may be “at odds with the Holy Father” on this subject. Pope John Paul II never said that capital punishment is intrinsically evil. On the contrary, he explicitly taught that it is not intrinsically evil. So, what Catholics who support capital punishment may legitimately be “at odds with” the pope about is not the question of whether capital punishment is intrinsically evil, since the pope never said that. The only thing left for them to be legitimately “at odds with” the pope about is whether capital punishment is advisable in practice – precisely what Msgr. Swetland falsely says Catholics cannotdisagree about.
Third, Cardinal Ratzinger’s statement that “it may still be permissible… to have recourse to capital punishment” is flatly incompatible with the claim that capital punishment is intrinsically wrong. It is quite ridiculous, then, for the monsignor to suggest that what Ratzinger is saying is that Catholics can disagree about whether capital punishment is intrinsically evil. His remarks in fact rule out the opinion that it is intrinsically evil!
Fourth, the context of Ratzinger’s 2004 statement was a presidential election in which there was public controversy over whether Catholic politicians who support abortion should be denied Holy Communion, whether Catholics who vote for candidates favoring capital punishment are comparable to Catholics who vote for candidates favoring abortion, whether voting for a candidate who supports abortion is formally cooperating in evil, etc. In other words, what was at issue was precisely the attitude Catholics ought to take toward certain actual practical policies, not abstract theoretical questions.
Since Msgr. Swetland puts emphasis on what the U.S. bishops, specifically, have said, it is also worth noting that a 2004 document put out by the United States Conference of Catholic Bishops and written by Archbishop William Levada (later to become Prefect of the CDF himself) repeats almost exactly the language of Cardinal Ratzinger’s remarks about the legitimate diversity of opinion on the matter of capital punishment.
In short, both the CDF and the USCCB have explicitly rejected Msgr. Swetland’s opinion that Catholics are obligated to oppose capital punishment in practice.
Some other bad arguments
Finally, let me address briefly some other remarks made by Msgr. Swetland during our debate. The monsignor suggested that the fact that the governments of Saudi Arabia, Iran, North Korea, Egypt, China, and other disreputable regimes apply capital punishment should make us wary of U.S. support for the practice.
But this is just silly. You might as well argue that opposition to abortion and “same-sex marriage” is suspect, on the grounds that such opposition is strongest in countries dominated by Islamists. Now, Msgr. Swetland is, of course, opposed to abortion and “same-sex marriage.” He would no doubt say, correctly, that Catholics should remain opposed to these things whether or not this puts them in some bad company. But Catholics who favor capital punishment can say exactly the same thing. That some bad regimes uphold capital punishment doesn’t show that there is anything wrong with capital punishment, any more than the fact that some of the same regimes oppose abortion and “same-sex marriage” shows that it is bad to oppose abortion and “same-sex marriage.”
In reply to the examples I gave of ways in which capital punishment deters certain kinds of murder, Msgr. Swetland alleged that this sort of argument would require extending the death penalty further and further until even petty theft is punishable by death.
But this objection is ridiculous. Is the monsignor saying that my position would as a matter of logical consistency require the execution of thieves? That is simply not the case. As Joe and I explain in the book, considerations of deterrence apply only after it has already been determined that a punishment is proportionate in its severity to the gravity of the offense. But capital punishment is not proportionate to the crime of petty theft. Hence it is ruled out from the get go, whether or not it would deter such theft.
Is the monsignor claiming instead merely that maintaining capital punishment will tend as a matter of contingent, sociologicalfact to lead to execution even for minor offenses? If so, then the claim is manifestly false, and the argument a textbook example of the slippery slope fallacy. Msgr. Swetland cites no causal mechanism – for example, no account of any sort of legal process or political developments – by which the execution of murderers will lead a society to start executing for petty theft and the like. Furthermore, many states in the U.S. have had capital punishment for decades or even centuries, and it has not led to the draconian applications the monsignor claims must follow.
Finally, I want to address the following remark Msgr. Swetland made during our exchange:
I find no imprimatur on this book and it is not Catholic teaching. You think it’s Catholic teaching but you didn’t bother to get an imprimatur, for good reason, no one would give you one, because it isn’t what the Church teaches.
End quote. Now, there are two problems with this statement. First, whether to get an imprimatur for the book was the publisher’s decision, and their general practice is not to seek an imprimatur except where canon law requires one. Since our book does not require one, the publisher did not seek one. That’s all. It was not a matter of trying to get an imprimatur and failing.
Second, the monsignor’s remark here is quite hypocritical. As I mentioned above, Msgr. Swetland contributed to an anthology on the subject of Catholicism and capital punishment, and he also relies on Brugger’s book on the subject. But neither of those books has an imprimatur either! So, if the monsignor does not take the absence of an imprimatur to be problematic in the case of these other books, he cannot consistently pretend that it is problematic in the case of mine.
In summary, then, Msgr. Swetland:
-endorses a positon (to the effect that capital punishment is intrinsically evil) that cannot be reconciled with scripture, the Fathers and Doctors of the Church, and the teaching of the popes, and which is therefore heterodox
-repeatedly declined to say whether or not he thinks scripture has taught moral error
-persistently ignored the crucial distinctions between development versus reversal of doctrine, scripture’s permitting something versus its positively commanding something, and changes in moral principle versus mere changes in prudential application of principle
-seriously misrepresents what Cardinal Ratzinger stated in his 2004 memorandum
-commits several other blatant fallacies.
I don’t want to be too hard on Msgr. Swetland. I don’t for a moment believe that he is deliberatelymisrepresenting or denying Catholic teaching. I believe that he is sincere and well-meaning. But I also believe that he is seriously confused, and that he is also sometimes unjust and uncharitable toward faithful Catholics who disagree with him. I also believe it is important, for the good of the Church, to call attention to the grave deficiencies in arguments like the ones he has given. When even a professional moral theologian who intends to be faithful to the Church presents arguments of such poor quality, it should be obvious that the pendulum has swung too far in the direction of abolitionism. Churchmen and other Catholics have for too long been relying on sentimentality and simple-minded slogans, and ignoring the vast wealth of scriptural, theological, philosophical, and social scientific arguments that support capital punishment. Part of the reason Joe and I wrote our book is to contribute to correcting this imbalance, and fostering a more sober and theologically responsible debate.
Published on July 20, 2017 19:26
July 14, 2017
Essence and existence

Published on July 14, 2017 11:24
McCaffrey and Murray on By Man Shall His Blood Be Shed

Published on July 14, 2017 11:21
July 10, 2017
Aquinas watches Glengarry Glen Ross

But it is Mamet’s script that is the key and the star of the picture. Superficially, it’s a movie about business. Really, though, it’s about manhood, or rather the aberrations thereof; and about the desperation to which men are led when they fail as men. There are no women onscreen in the movie at all. But for several of the characters, there is a woman lurking behind the scenes whose presence is more keenly felt for being only implicit – for one man, as a momentary object of desire; for another man, as someone he needs to protect and provide for; for a third man, as the one who really wears the trousers.
The characters are extreme. In real life, few salesmen are as cringe-makingly phony as Jack Lemmon’s Shelley Levene. Few superiors are as breathtakingly abusive as Alec Baldwin’s Blake. Few husbands are as pathetically whipped as Jonathan Pryce’s James Lingk. Even in 2017, few men are quite as foul-mouthed as Al Pacino’s Ricky Roma.
But the visual and literary arts work by means of such skillful caricatures. They abstract simple general patterns from concrete reality, wherein they are mixed with various particular and complicating circumstances. Then they take these patterns and re-embody them in a visual or verbal representation, so that we might consider them more closely and free of the messy, distracting subtleties of real life. When done well, the result is an idealization conveyed via the illusion of realism. Levene is like the Platonic Form of Sleazy Salesman, Blake is like the Form of Abusive Manager, and so forth. But each is written and portrayed so skillfully that they seem like concrete human beings. (To take one of the few sequences from the film devoid of bad language, consider the exchange between Levene and Larry Spannel. Painful to watch, it conveys perfectly the dynamic between salesman and customer, even if real-world exchanges are rarely this awkward.)
Aquinas famously holds that “beautiful things are those which please when seen” (Summa Theologiae I.5.4). The “seeing” in question is not primarily that done with the eye, but rather that done with the intellect. And what the intellect sees and takes pleasure in are the integrity, proportion, and clarity of the thing perceived as beautiful (ST I.39.8). Let’s walk Glengarry through these three criteria:
1. Integrity: What Aquinas has in mind here is the perfection or completion of a thing, such as the perfection a good specimen of some kind of animal exhibits or the completeness a fully developed specimen exhibits. A horse is beautiful, but less so if it is missing a leg or some other part, or if it is still in its embryonic stage.
Now, as already noted, Glengarry’s characters are extreme, and one sense in which they are is that they exhibit in an especially full or complete way certain character traits, albeit negative ones. Levene is the perfectly sleazy and insincere salesman, Blake the perfectly cruel manager, Lingk the perfectly weak man, and so forth. Or at least, they are perfectly so to the extent consistent with being a realistic and therefore still believable instance of a salesman, manager, etc. Part of what is aesthetically attractive about these characters, then, is that they enable us to consider and contemplate what it is to have these various character traits in their fullness.
(Naturally, I am using “perfection” here in an extended and analogical sense, since vicious character traits are of course in the strictest sense imperfections. Blake, in his extreme abusiveness, is imperfect qua human being, but “perfect” qua thug.)
There is also a kind of “perfection,” in the sense of fullness or completeness, in the low state to which some of the characters are reduced. The humiliation to which Kevin Spacey’s character John Williamson is reduced by Roma’s utterly crushing tirade is something like perfect humiliation. The pretentious, convoluted, bold-as-brass farrago of BS by which Roma sucks Lingk into a real estate deal and tries to keep him there is perfect BS. The helplessness, emasculation, and despair to which Levene is reduced by the end of the film is something like perfect misery. (Again, in the extended sense of the term “perfect.”)
Consider also that the extreme obscenity and profanity the script is notorious for is largely confined to the “alpha males” or would-be alpha males. The worst cases are Blake and Roma, who are precisely the two dominant men in the story. Next are Levene, who was oncetop dog and is now past his prime; and Ed Harris’s Dave Moss, who would very much like to be top dog but can never seem to pull it off. By contrast, the “beta males” of the story – Lingk and Alan Arkin’s George Aaronow – do little if any cussing at all; and the characters of intermediate status (such as Williamson) are also more or less intermediate in the amount of cussing they do. The rough language is a mark of the “perfection” or completeness of the aggressiveness and swagger characteristic of distorted masculinity. (Note the way Roma’s choice of words in his stinging rant against Williamson – “c**t,” “fairy,” “f**ing child,” etc. -- is intended precisely to strip the latter of his manhood.)
No one would want to be a person of one of these kinds, or to be in the situations they find themselves in. But we do want to understand them, and the perfection or completeness they represent helps us precisely to do that, which is one reason the film is aesthetically pleasing despite its unpleasant subject matter.
2. Proportion: By this criterion, what Aquinas has in mind is order, and in the context of a good story this would be manifest in the coherence and structure of its plot, the development of its characters, the quality of the dialogue, and so forth.
In Glengarry, we have several instances of such order. We have a simple, unifying principle ordering the actions of the characters and driving the story – the imperative to make a big sale within a week, at any cost, or lose employment. We have Levene’s character arc from desperation and near despair up to apparent triumph and elation and finally back down again to utter failure and total, unmitigated despair. We have the symmetry of Roma and Aaranow, the top man and bottom man in the office respectively, ending up the only survivors of the sales competition. We have the justice of Levene and Moss, who resort to crime in order to maintain their place in the company, facing swift retribution. We have Lingk’s progression from a quietly insecure man to an utterly frightened, confused, and frantic man – from a deer in the headlights to a deer stuffed and mounted, as it were. We have the banality of sales office life as represented at the beginning of the film rudely interrupted by Blake’s bracing challenge and the events that follow upon it, only to end the film with a return to banality. We have Mamet’s perfectly crafted dialogue, in which every pause, stammer, and verbal tic is thought through and intended to be spoken by the actors exactly as written.
3. Clarity: As I’ve said, the movie abstracts from concrete reality certain general character types, purges from them the nuance and complexity in which we find these general patterns embedded in everyday life, and re-embodies them in extreme characters so that we might more carefully consider those types. Just as we know more clearly what it is to be a triangle by abstracting from particular triangles (red ones, green ones, triangles drawn in ink, triangles drawn in chalk, etc.) and considering the general pattern, so too does the movie allow us to see more clearly what it is to be a desperate man, a cruel man, a weak man, a dishonest man, a broken man, and so on, by way of its skillful caricatures.
So, in its integrity, proportion, and clarity, Glengarryhas the marks of a beautiful thing, despite its grim subject matter. One need not admire and approve of Satan in order to admire and approve of Dante’s or Milton’s literary representations of Satan, and one need not admire or approve of the sorts of people represented in a film like Glengarry in order to admire and approve of the representation itself.
Examples of this sort of artistic beauty are interesting in themselves, and also because they help us more deeply to understand the nature of beauty. In a sentimental culture like our own, the notion of beauty, like that of love, is often misunderstood. Like love, beauty is often taken to be something schmaltzy, and certainly to be something that appeals primarily to the affective side of our nature. But as with love, that is in fact not the case. Love is primarily a matter of the will, even though it has, of course, an affective side. And beauty is primarily a matter of the intellect, even though it too has an affective side.
When the object of an artistic representation is itself beautiful – a beautiful woman, say, or a beautiful natural setting – it can seem that it is what the senses take in, rather than what the intellect grasps, that primarily accounts for the beauty of the representation. But when the object of the representation is ugly, and yet we nevertheless judge the representation itself to be beautiful, the intellect’s essential role in the perception of beauty is more evident. The intellect “sees past” the ugliness of the object of the representation and focuses instead on the virtues of the representation itself.
One way to understand kitsch is as art that leans too heavily on the sensory and affective aspects of a work of art and too little on the content that the intellect alone can grasp, and which is thus superficial. And one way to understand modern art is as an overcompensation in the opposite direction. The modern artist wants to avoid kitsch but often falls into the opposite error of making art an entirely theoretical exercise that can appeal only to the intellect and not at all to our senses or passions. Hence the obsession with highly abstract modes of representation or with extremely ugly subject matter. Art becomes meta-art (a phenomenon I have discussed here and here).
As this indicates, there are limits to the distance that can exist between the sensory and affective content of a work of art on the one hand, and its intellectual content on the other, if it is to be capable of real beauty. To be sure, I am not claiming that there is a limit to the ugliness of the objectof the representation – again, even a literary representation of Satan can be beautiful (as in Dante or Milton), despite Satan’s being maximally repulsive himself. But there are nevertheless ways of representing what is ugly that are themselves so ugly that the representation cannot be beautiful. This is what happens in works of art that reflect an essentially nihilistic or transgressive spirit. The aim in such depraved art is not to convey truth or represent reality (as Glengarrydoes) but rather to “do dirt” on reality and “give the finger” to some hated truth. But that is a subject worth a post of its own.
[Interested readers can find links to earlier posts on movies, art, and pop culture in general collected here.]
Published on July 10, 2017 09:57
Edward Feser's Blog
- Edward Feser's profile
- 325 followers
Edward Feser isn't a Goodreads Author
(yet),
but they
do have a blog,
so here are some recent posts imported from
their feed.
