Peter Smith's Blog, page 135
December 22, 2010
Florence, for body and soul

Piazza del Duomo
Florence in winter is a delight. You can get even into the Uffizi without queuing. Stand quietly in front of your favourite paintings or frescos for as long as you like without crowds around you all the time. And when you feel like feeding body rather than soul, get into decent restaurants which are half-empty. It can certainly be cold: but with luck, you'll be able to walk around under blue skies. We hadn't expected snow, though! Nor had the Florentines, judging by the way everything ground to a complete halt for a day. But it did all look wonderful.
If you happen to be in Tuscany before January 23, do go to the Bronzino exhibition at Palazzo Strozzi. It is a unique opportunity to see some 80% of Bronzino's surviving paintings together. And the exhibition is quite beautifully put together and wonderfully presented (the contrast with the Uffizi's dreadfully drear hanging could hardly be greater). And if you have the chance, get yourself on one of the weekly tours of the Contini Bonacossi collection acquired by the Uffizi a dozen years ago and still not on general display. It includes the wonderful Veronese portrait of Iseppo da Porto and his young son which we liked so much at the Louvre last year.
We ate well (surprise, surprise). These are the three places we'll definitely go back to (and they will still be there after January 23rd, so make a note!):
Cibrèino (Trattoria Cibrèo) Via de' Macci 122/r. This shares a kitchen of the very expensive Cibrèo restaurant next door: but you will eat as well for less than half the price. (You can't book, and might have to share a table if there are only two of you.)
Olio & Convivium Via Santo Spirito 4. A modern take on Tuscan food — we liked the atmosphere, the food, and the stunning wine list.
Cantinetta dei Verrazzano Via dei Tavolini, 18/r. Fantastic place if you want a light (not cheap!) lunch.
December 21, 2010
A room with a view
Well, that isn't supposed to happen. Heavy snow in Florence before Christmas. The city cut off. The airports closed.
But there are far worse places to be forced to stay a couple more days than planned. The galleries and the churches were still open more or less when they were supposed to be; the restaurants still a delight; and our welcoming and very comfortable hotel had no problem letting us stay on a couple of days (and we indeed had the very room that was used in the film A Room With a View: here's the Ponte Vecchio from our terrace, the day after the snow.)
There were of course other tourists still around; but we were a sprinkling among real Florence out and about doing its Christmas shopping. Even the Uffizi was quiet. Still, after six nights, you begin to suffer from visual overload, and even I find that the thought of yet another meal out begins to pall. So it was good to get back last night to an equally snowy Cambridge.
December 12, 2010
On teaching philosophy
I've just added some long comments of my own to the exchange between Tom Stoneham and Paul Noordhof in the comments thread here. Perhaps of most interest to UK philosophers, but do read and join in the discussion!
December 5, 2010
Jane Austen and moral philosophy
I'm one of the panelists on the Ask Philosophers website. And I'm amused to find that three particular favourites of mine happen to be the topics of my last three responses, namely the philosophy of maths, wine, and Jane Austen.
And how does Austen come in for a mention? Well, someone who'd evidently enjoyed reading Camus' The Plague was asking for suggestions of other novels with "philosophical underpinnings". So — perhaps not at all the sort of answer s/he was expecting — I first offered Jane Austen (pretty much any of her novels will do, though my favourite is Emma). Now,
I am not going to try to make out that Jane Austen was a philosopher or even a philosopher manquée. But … she was interested from the south side in some quite general or theoretical problems about human nature and conduct in which philosophers proper were and are interested from the north side.
The very titles of some her novels indicate their moral concerns. Thus
Sense and Sensibility really is about the relations between Sense and Sensibility or, as we might put it, between Head and Heart, Thought and Feeling, Judgement and Emotion, or Sensibleness and Sensitiveness.
And there are correspondingly thematic framings in other novels, even those without abstract nouns in their titles. Thus
If cacophony had not forbidden, Emma could and I think would have been entitled Influence and Interference. Or it might have been called more generically Solicitude. Jane Austen's question here was: What makes it sometimes legitimate or even obligatory for one person deliberately to try to modify the course of another person's life, while sometimes such attempts are wrong? Where is the line between Meddling and Helping? Or, more generally, between proper and improper solicitude and unsolicitude about the destinies and welfares of others? Why was Emma wrong to try to arrange Harriet's life, when Mr Knightley was right to try to improve Emma's mind and character? Jane Austen's answer is the right answer. Emma was treating Harriet as a puppet to be worked by hidden strings. Mr Knightley advised and scolded Emma to her face. Emma knew what Mr Knightley required of her and hoped for her. Harriet was not to know what Emma was scheming on her behalf. Mr Knightley dealt with Emma as a potentially responsible and rational being. Emma dealt with Harriet as a doll. Proper solicitude is open and not secret. Furthermore, proper solicitude is actuated by genuine good will. Improper solicitude is actuated by love of power, jealousy, conceit, sentimentality and so on.
The minor characters in Emma too are 'systematically described in terms of their different kinds or degrees of concernment or unconcernment with the lives of others.' And Austen's treatment of her themes is guided by what we might call an Aristotelian conception of the gradations of the many virtues as opposed to a black and white, saint vs sinner, Calvanist morality.
[T]he Aristotelian pattern of ethical ideas represents people as differing from one another in degree and not in kind, and differing from one another not in respect just of a single generic Sunday attribute, Goodness, say, or else Wickedness, but in respect of a whole spectrum of specific week-day attributes. A is a bit more irritable and ambitious than B, but less indolent and less sentimental. C is meaner and quicker-witted than D, and D is greedier and more athletic than C. And so on. A person is not black or white, but iridescent with all the colours of the rainbow; and he is not a flat plane, but a highly irregular solid. He is not blankly Good or Bad, blankly angelic or fiendish; he is better than most in one respect, about level with the average in another respect, and a bit, perhaps a big bit, deficient in a third respect. In fact he is like the people we really know, in a way in which we do not know and could not know any people who are just Bad or else just Good.
Jane Austen's moral ideas are, with certain exceptions, ideas of the Aristotelian and not of the Calvinist pattern. Much though she had learned from Johnson, this she had not learned from him. When Johnson is being ethically solemn, he draws people in black and white. So they never come to life, any more than the North Pole and the South Pole display any scenic features. Jane Austen's people are, nearly always, alive all over, all through and all round, displaying admirably or amusingly or deplorably proportioned mixtures of all the colours that there are, save pure White and pure Black. If a Calvinist critic were to ask us whether Mr Collins was Hell-bound or Heaven-bent, we could not answer. The question does not apply. Mr Collins belongs to neither pole; he belongs to a very particular parish in the English Midlands. He is a stupid, complacent and inflated ass, but a Sinner? No. A Saint? No. He is just a ridiculous figure, that is, a figure for which the Calvinist ethical psychology does not cater. The questions Was Emma Good? Was she Bad? are equally unanswerable and equally uninteresting. Obviously she should have been smacked more often when young; obviously, too, eternal Hell-fire is not required for her.
You can tell from persons being "he" and the cheery talking of smacking that that the essay from which all those sane and insightful quotations are taken wasn't written quite yesterday. But the piece is by a good philosopher who is perhaps less read now than he should be. For a treat, for those who don't know his wonderful essay 'Jane Austen and the Moralists', I've linked to a PDF of it. (And if after reading further, you still don't recognize the author's voice, then a quick Google search will reveal him.)
Exercise: now write in Austenian style brief reflections on the morality of thus further expediting the circulation of an old piece that is already only a couple of clicks away from any knowledgeable searcher.
December 3, 2010
Students are right to be pissed off …
… about the proposed "reforms" to higher education funding. I've started a couple of times to write a blog-post adding my two-pennyworth of comment. But firstly, I get too depressed musing more generally about the whole awfulness of various education "reforms" over the last forty or so years (at my most charitable, let's say quite spectacular object lessons in the Law of Unintended Consequences). And second, much of what I might say has in fact already been said, and said well, by others — e.g. by Stefan Collini on 'Browne's Gamble', John Sutherland, writing under the cheery title English degrees for £27k – who's buying?, and particularly by Iain Pears on 'How the Humanities'.
Iain Pears's point about re-centering the business of humanities departments on teaching strikes a chord with me, as I approach the finishing-line with my job. It is difficult to credit now, but when I started as a lecturer we really had only half a day's "induction" course — and one element of that was a talk on Arnold, Newman and Leavis on the idea of a university (can you imagine?). And we did mostly thought of ourselves as committed university teachers, and took it for granted that we would spent a lot of time on our students. 'Research' (as opposed to 'scholarship', i.e. keeping up our reading and thinking) was something to be done in our — admittedly generous — spare time. Certainly, the idea that research in the humanities — yet another article in some minor passing debate, yet another unnecessary book? — should be at the very centre of everything, and teaching something to be avoided as much as possible (by getting research grants) was yet to come.
It wouldn't be such a bad thing — and will be the least we owe to the kids who have to mortgage their futures to study with us — if in this one respect at any rate we went forward to the past.
November 28, 2010
Cambridge Principia Symposium
A while back, a number of us had the thought that we ought to do something in Cambridge to mark the centenary of Principia. But organizing blockbuster conferences is always a real pain; and to hold them here you need arrange everything years in advance; and in any case, to be frank, big conferences are very often just not worth the effort. So we thought, well, let's perhaps organize something small and relatively informal nearer the time. Then time passed and the centenary date got nearer. And more time passed. And in fact the occasion would in the end have gone unmarked, except that Nik Sultana — a grad student in Comp. Sci.– took up the idea late in the day and made it all happen. All credit to him. Here's the programme, some abstracts, and links to some short papers.
Given Nik's roots in computer science, there was a somewhat different spin to this symposium than it would have had if organized just by a logic-minded philosopher or a philosophy-minded logician. Though, truth to tell, I'm not sure I learnt a great deal from the comp. sci. orientated talks. Formal proof checkers are developing apace, and this work on formal proofs is beginning to impact on 'mainstream' mathematics. But I basically knew that, though I got to hear about a few interesting details.
Three random thoughts. (1) When people talk about "type theories" they tend to really mean theories-with-type-disciplines rather than a theory-about-types: wouldn't "typed theories" have been better? (2) Like others who have learnt from Great Uncle Frege, I did find the wobbling between talk of functions and talk of expressions-for-functions by some people rather uncomfortable. (3) [Arising from some responses to Byeong-uk Yi's talk], people are really unhappy with the idea that plural terms might refer, plurally, to several things rather than being disguised singular reference to a set: singularist prejudice goes deep.
The stand-out paper for me, though, was my colleague Michael Potter's talk about two ideas of ambiguity in Principia — the idea of "real" (i.e. unbound) variables as being ambiguous or variable names, and the idea of (most) "theorems" of PM in fact being type-ambiguous. The first evidences a step back from Frege's clarity about the role of "variables" as anaphoric pronouns. The second has the authors of Principia struggling towards the idea of using schemas in the modern sense. Michael had some interesting quotes from correspondence between Whitehead and Russell, in which Whitehead is pressing towards the idea of a generalization using a metalanguistic schema, in using which you stand outside the given formalized language, and Russell (more wedded to a logical monism?) resisting. This was interesting stuff, with some nice historical detail, and I hope Michael works it up further.
November 24, 2010
Cuts, consistency and axiomatized theories
In the Wednesday Logic Reading Group, where we are working through Sara Negri and Jan von Plato's Structural Proof Theory, I today introduced Chapter 6, 'Structural Proof Analysis of Axiomatic Theories'. In their commendable efforts to be brief, the authors are sometimes a bit brisk about motivation. So I thought it was worth trying to stand back a bit from the details of this action-packed chapter as far as I understood it in the few hours I had to prepare, and to try to give an overall sense of the project. These are the notes I wrote for myself. As often with such middle-of-term efforts dashed off in a couple of hours, I both would have liked to do better and do more justice to what we are reading, but I also just don't have time to do more now than make a few corrections to the first version. The logic enthusiasts at the seminar seemed to find the remarks useful, though, so for what they are worth here there are. The usual warning applies: caveat lector.
November 19, 2010
Godel Without (Too Many) Tears. Episodes 5 & 6
Here are the handouts for the last two Gödel lectures:
5. Primitive recursive functions
6. Expressing and capturing the primitive recursive functions
(These two haven't changed greatly from the previous versions from earlier in the year.)
Mary Leng's Mathematics and Reality, Chs 5 & 6
We are reading Mary Leng's book in the Thursday Logic Seminar for the second part of term. It fell to me to introduce discussion of Chapters 5 and 6, and I found myself yesterday writing (very rapidly indeed) these brisk notes in trying to get my own thoughts clearer before the meeting. There was an excellent discussion which has led to a few after-the-event changes. But mostly these notes stay in the same rough-and-ready form, and I'm not going to have time to do better: so caveat lector! However, they might be of some interest to others intrigued by Mary's project.
November 13, 2010
Intro Logic Lectures
Here's another helping of the overheads for my first first-year logic lectures 4 to 10 this term. This is the block of seven lectures on basic propositional logic via truth-tables. I've already posted the very links to the first three very introductory ones — though you can catch up here. The new slides are "dynamic", revealing one bullet point at a time because there is often over-writing, or the dynamic filling-in of truth-tables etc.: for the best effect, select "View > Page Display > Single Page" in Adobe Reader.
The overheads are there to help speed things up, rescue students from having to read my terrible blackboard writing, and to keep me on message. Needless to say, I do embroider around and about them in the live show, and throw in other remarks as the mood takes me. So the content of the overheads is pretty basic and conventional. Don't expect wild excitements! But for what they are worth, here they are:
Three Connectives
Bivalence; Evaluating Propositions
How to Test Arguments, a Sketch; Introducing PL
Tautologies
Tautological Entailment
The Material Conditional
'Only if'; The Expressive Adequacy Theorem