Peter Smith's Blog, page 133
February 2, 2011
Brandom's incompatibility semantics, and other distractions
First, apologies to Alan Weir and all his fans who are impatiently awaiting the next episode of my stalled discussion of his book. I will get back to it, but I have been distracted over the last couple of weeks by various events, both in good ways and in less enlivening ways.
On the debit side, it now seems definite that I'm going to get replaced on retirement by someone remote from anything to do with logic, even very broadly construed (that's assuming I eventually get replaced at all). Difficult not to get a bit depressed by such developments, about which no doubt more anon. Let's just say it's a very great pity, given the flourishing of logicky enterprises here, that we don't back successes.
On the plus side, one distraction has been starting a close-reading of Kaye's classic Models of Peano Arithmetic for our math logic reading group (I know the book a bit, of course, but it is different when you have to give presentations to a seminar on what exactly is going on and why). Another distraction — more time consuming but still enjoyable — was the recent annual grad conference here in the philosophy of logic and mathematics. The format is that, apart from the keynote speakers, grads from various places give papers, and locals give responses. I was replying to a nice talk by Giacomo Turbanti on modality in Brandom's semantics, which forced me to do an amount of reading up, because I wanted to give a scene-setting talk to help those who hadn't come across Brandom's project before. In retrospect, having had the chance to think a bit more, I realize what I said wasn't spot on in certain respects, so I won't post my talk here as I was planning. But here's one general comment I stand by, and one techie query for anyone who knows about this stuff.
The comment is this. The familiar inferentialist approach to the logical operators takes as its setting a standard consequence relation, and then adds introduction rules for the operator O which tell us when we are canonically entitled to assert a sentence with O dominant. Then we are supposed to locate the harmonious elimination rule which enables us get from a sentence with O dominant to wherever we could have got from its canonical grounds. Now, this kind of inferentialist approach to characterizing the logical operators by their introduction and harmonious elimination rules delivers intuitionistic logic but not full classical negation. Or so the usual story goes, as worked out in the hands of Prawitz, Dummett and Tennant. Brandom, though, claims that his brand of incoherence-based inferentialism does deliver classical logic. How does he pull a classically shaped rabbit out of an inferentialist hat?
Part of the story is that he in effect gives rejection rules rather than assertion rules for connectives. What Brandom's rule for negation (for example) does is, in effect, tell us when to reject a proposition with negation its main operator, because adding it to some other stuff would lead to incoherence. But why privilege rules of rejection over rules for assertion? Why is this any better than privileging rules of assertion over rules for rejection? I would have thought that if — like Brandom — we see sapient enquiries responding to challenges and developing arguments in response, we should at most be giving equal weight to the rejections and inconsistencies that prompt a reasoned response as to the assertions and deductions they elicit. But developing that line of thought would take us in the direction of Timothy Smiley and Ian Rumfitt's bilateralism which puts assertion and denial on a par. Then we do arguably get an inferentialist framework which is genuinely friendly to classical logic. Why doesn't Brandom go down this route, given his starting point, I wonder?
The techie question is this. Suppose we start out with a standard single-conclusion consequence relation S |- A between finite sets of propositions S and propositions A, where "standard" means we have reflexivity, i.e. {A} |- A, dilution on the left, and cut.
Now we can define the extensional property Inc of being a (Post)-inconsistent finite set of sentences by saying that finite S is in Inc just if S |- A for all A (of the relevant language). It is immediate that Inc satisfies the filter condition that Brandom calls persistence, meaning that if S is in Inc, and S* is a superset of S, then S* is in Inc.
We can also go the other way about. We can start (as indeed Brandom wants to) with the idea of an upwardly closed set of sets of sentences Inc, and define a relation S |= A to hold just in case, for every set of sentences D, if D + A is in Inc so is D + S. It is easy to check that, so defined, |= is a standard consequence relation.
In the general case, however, if we start from a consequence relation |-, define Inc as suggested (using the idea of Post inconsistency), and then define |= from Inc, we don't get back to where we started. We will have S |- A entails S |= A, but not always vice versa. So here's the techie query (and someone out there must know this!): under what general conditions does the round trip take us in a closed circle, so S |- A iff S |= A? The relevant language having a classical negation will suffice, but what is the weakest condition? (Maybe Brandom himself tells us, and I should have been more patient hacking through his stuff: but the mode of presentation in the appendix to the fifth Locke Lecture is pretty much a paradigm of how not to present logical results in a helpful way.)
January 17, 2011
Weir on formalism in SEP
While waiting for the next exciting instalment of my comments on his Truth Through Proof, you might like to look at Alan Weir's brand new entry on formalism in the philosophy of maths for the ever-more-wonderful Stanford Encyclopedia.
January 15, 2011
GWT updated
The first two episodes of Gödel Without Tears have been corrected — catching a few typos but mainly to correct the silly thinko that David Makinson caught. And there are new versions of episodes 7 (Arithmetization of Syntax) and 8 (The First Incompleteness Theorem), though these aren't much changed from last year's NZ version. Go to the GWT page.
January 14, 2011
Oops! A blunder in GWT
David Makinson has emailed to point out a foul-up in Episode 2, §9, of Gödel Without Tears. (Actually, he very kindly called it an "anomaly". This suggests one of those irregular conjugations: "I made a little slip, what you wrote involves an anomaly, he or she made a terrible blunder".)
Since I picked up the email on a train to London I had a few hours to worry about whether the same foul-up occurs in my Gödel book (in the corresponding §7.1). Phew. It doesn't. It was indeed something too unthinkingly said as an aside in lectures, and afterwards plonked down in the notes. Which is a relief.
I'll rewrite the relevant passage in Gödel Without Tears a.s.a.p. But here's the basic story. Theorem 5 says: A consistent, sufficiently strong, axiomatized formal theory cannot be negation complete. Here, 'sufficient strength' you will recall is a matter of being able to capture or represent decidable properties of numbers, and 'axiomatized' of course means 'decidably axiomatized'.
Now neither this theorem nor the proof I gave of it actually delivers us a formally undecidable sentence. So it is weaker than a full Gödelian result. But I said more:
So suppose we start off with a consistent 'sufficiently strong' theory T couched in some language which just talks about arithmetic matters: then this theory T is incomplete, and will have arithmetical formally undecidable sentences. But now imagine that we extend T 's language (perhaps it now talks about sets of numbers as well as about numbers), and we give it richer axioms, to arrive at an expanded consistent theory U. U will still be sufficiently strong if T is, and so Theorem 5 will still apply if it is properly axiomatized. Note, however, that as far as Theorem 5 is concerned, it could be that U repairs the gaps in T and proves every truth statable in T's language, while the incompleteness has now 'moved outwards', so to speak, to claims involving U's new vocabulary.
If that were right, it would be another way Theorem 5 is weaker than Gödel, for he shows that some incompleteness will always remain even in the theory's arithmetical core. But it isn't right. Sigh. Here's David's counter, only slightly edited:
Let T* be the set of all theorems of U in the language of T. Since T is included in T* which is included in U, we know that T* is sufficiently strong but consistent. And suppose for reductio that T* is negation complete in the language of T; we get a contradiction.
If T* is negation complete then T* must be decidable [by the same kind of argument used in proving Theorem 3]. Thus, given any sentence A in the language of T, just grind out theorems of U until you get either A or its negation (which you must, since T* is included in U and by supposition is negation complete in its language). But if T* is decidable, then it may serve as the axiom set for itself as a axiomatized formal theory. Thus T* is a consistent, sufficiently strong, axiomatized formal theory and so by Theorem 5 is not negation complete after all, giving us a contradiction.
Indeed. Oh dear, I've been leading the youth astray again …
January 12, 2011
TTP, CUP, and a shiny new MBA
I suppose it was mildly daft to plunge into blogging about Alan Weir's TTP just as the beginning of term looms. There's now a flurry of other things which I really need to be thinking about, just as I'm getting into the book, and puzzling through the next chapter. There's admin as Chair of Examiners for Tripos to be done, plus putting together some handouts for my last lectures on Gödel's Theorems (the last for this academic year, at any rate), thinking about the response I'm down to give to one of the papers at the Phil. Logic & Maths conference here (about Brandom of all people), and that's not to mention sorting out the techie logic seminar and preparing an initial talk to that. So the discussion of Alan's book will stutter a bit for the next couple of weeks. Sorry about that.
For light relief, it is time for trips to the CUP Bookshop sale again. This is a great annual institution which I've mentioned before. The Press damage some books by stamping "damaged" across the title page, and then flog them (this year) at £3 for any paperback and £7 for any hardback. And during the week or ten days of the sale they keep putting out new stock in a random way, so you have to keep slipping back, just in case … It is amazing what turns up.
However, having badly run out of book shelving space, and then some, I really really do have to restrain myself. But I couldn't resist the 'Cambridge Companions' to Haydn and Schubert, and David Crystal's fun-if-you-like-that-kind-of-thing book on Shakespeare's language.
And, erm, another category theory tome. Despite all the empirical evidence, I think I must subconsciously believe in a magical theory of learning-by-osmosis. Put the book on your shelves and the knowledge slowly seeps in … doesn't it?
As for the MBA, that is, of course, a MacBook Air to you. Let me just say that the new version is awesome. I had an original version MBA, which was lovely but s-l-o-w and had a pretty poor battery life. But I've been given one of the new models, and the difference is impressive (it is the machine the original one almost promised to be, but fell quite a bit short of). Subjectively very fast, wonderful screen, and ludicrously long-lasting battery for academic writing/reading/surfing/mailing use. (For fellow Appleheads: I have the 13″, as I find the visual proportions of the 11.6″ unhappy — I can't shake the sense of peering through a letter box — and I want big-enough side-by-side LaTeX windows. The base configuration with 2gb memory is more than just fine if you are not doing anything very fancy with it. If you have been wavering, treat yourself.)
January 9, 2011
TTP, 4. §1.III: Sense, circumstance, world
In the present section, Weir says something about the kind of semantic framework he favours, and in particular about issues of context-sensitivity.
The basic idea is very familiar. "Utterances of declarative sentences are typically true or false, and what makes them one or the other is, in general, a triple product of firstly the Sinn or informational content they express, secondly the circumstances of the utterance, and finally the way the world is". So this is the usual modern twist on the ur-Fregean story: it isn't just sense, but sense plus context (broadly construed), that determines reference and so fixes truth-conditions. This basic picture is widely endorsed, and Weir doesn't aim to develop a detailed account of how the three layers of story interrelate. Some general remarks are enough for his purposes.
Suppose we aim for a systematic story about how a certain class of sentences gets its truth conditions, for example those involving a demonstrative 'that'. The systematic story will, perhaps, use a notion like salience, so for example it tells us that 'that man is clever' is true when the most salient man in the context is clever. Now, for this to be part of a semantic theory that is explanantory of speech-behaviour, speakers will have to reveal appropriate sensitivity to what we theorists would call considerations of salience. But those we are interpreting needn't themselves have the concept of salience. And the explanatory statement of truth-conditions is not synonymous with 'that man is clever'. We thus need to distinguish the literal content of the sentence as speakers understand it (what is shared by literal translation, for example) from the explanatory truth-conditions delivered by our systematic semantic theory.
Note though, semantics is one thing, metaphysics something else. It might be that what it takes (according to semantic theory) for 'that man is clever' to be true is that the most salient man in the context is clever. But what has to exist for that to be the case? — does it require the existence, for example, of a truth-making fact? Semantics is silent on the issue: so, for example, fans and foes of truth-makers can alike accept the same semantic story about explanatory truth-conditions.
Now, 'literal content' vs 'explanatory truth-conditions' was, Weir tells us (fn. 28) his own originally preferred terminology here. He now thinks 'informational content' or 'sense' vs 'metaphysical content' is less misleading. Really? Does dubbing something 'metaphysical' ever make things clearer?? Especially when you've just used 'metaphysical' in a significantly different way in talking of metaphysical realism, and also insisted on downplaying the metaphysical loading of the semantic story??? But let's not get fractious! — there is a distinction to be made, whatever we call it. Though let's also be on the watch for occasions where the possibly tendentious labelling is allowed to carry argumentative weight.
As Weir says, not everyone endorses the sense/circumstances/world (SCW) picture. There are radical contextualists who don't like the idea of a given sense or meaning making a fixed contribution to determining truth-conditions. Weir "side[s] with those who hold that radical contextualism makes language grasp a mystery".
However, even given the SCW picture, there is room for debate about how much work circumstances do, how much context-relativity we need to recognize. Cappelen and Lepore, for example, have argued that there is only a rather confined Basic Set of context-sensitive expressions in language, contra those who seek philosophical illumination by finding hidden context sensitivity. Weir hints that he is going to need to take a more generous line than Cappelen and Lepore (without falling into radical contextualism). But we'll have to wait to see how this works.
A final comment. Weir's anti-realism about mathematics, as we saw, is to be a built on a distinction between representational and non-representational modes of discourse. And on the face of it, you would expect that issues about different modes of discourse would be orthogonal to the issues about kinds of context-sensitivity most highlighted in this section. We'll also have to see just see what connections get forged. True, there is a murky hint on p. 38; but it didn't at all help this reader. (I suppose a more Wittgensteinian pragmatist who emphasizes the different roles of different discourses might worry that Weir seems to be too inclined to privilege the representational discourse for which the SCW picture seems natural.)
January 5, 2011
TTP, 3. §§1.I–II: Realisms
As we can see from our initial specification of his position, to get Weir's philosophy of mathematics to fly will involve accepting some substantial and potentially controversial claims in the philosophy of language and metaphysics. The first two chapters of TTP fill in some of the needed background. Weir starts by talking a bit about realism(s). Given that, in the Introduction at p. 6, he has already characterized himself as aiming for "an anti-realist … reading of mathematics", we should get clear about what kind of realism he is anti.
However, I didn't find the ensuing discussion altogether clear (is it perhaps extracted from something longer?). So in what follows, I'm reconstructing a little, but hopefully in a broadly sympathetic way, for I do at least want to end up pretty much where Weir does.
Traditional realisms, he says, "affirm the mind-independent existence of some sort of entity". But what does 'mind-independent' mean here? The problems are immediate. For a start, which kinds of minds count? On the one hand, if it's just finite sublunary minds, then Berkeley comes out a realist, which isn't what we want (Weir himself contrasts realism with idealism). On the other hand — Weir might have noted — if we agree with Berkeley and count God as among the minds, then any traditional theist who believes that the physical world is dependent for its existence on God would ipso facto count as an non-realist about sticks and stones, which is also surely not what we want. Then there are other problems with the traditional formulation: on a crude reading, it seems to define away the very possibility of being a realist about minds.
Let's put those worries on hold just for a moment, and turn to consider the modern theme that realism should instead best be characterized in epistemic terms. Thus Dummett (quoted by Weir): 'Realism I characterise as the belief that statements … possess an objective truth value, independently of our means of knowing it.' Of course, others such as Devitt have emphatically insisted contra Dummett that realism about Xs, properly understood, is an ontological doctrine about what there is, and is not to be confused with any epistemic or semantic doctrine. Where does Weir stand on this?
Well, he spends some time discussing the idea that realism is a species of fallibilism. We can present this sort of realism about a region of discourse R schematically as saying
For every (or some?) R-sentence s, it is possible (what kind of possibility?) for speakers (which speakers? even in optimal conditions?) to believe s though it is not true, or disbelieve s though it not false.
There are four dimensions along which versions of realism-as-fallibilism can vary, corresponding to the four queries. And Weir doesn't hold out much hope that there is any way of setting the variables to give us a thesis which is substantive enough to be interesting but also sufficiently captures what a realist is after. He offers a number of considerations. Embroidering a bit, we could perhaps put one of them like this. Suppose we keep fixed our view about the nature of Xs but change our mind about the quality of our epistemic access to Xs. Suppose we become very optimistic — perhaps implausibly over-optimistic — and now think that, at least when we are optimally placed and exercising our cognitive faculties in the optimal way, there are (enough) claims about Xs which (in the relevant sense of 'possible') it is not possible for us to go wrong about. Then, the thought goes, surely changing our view like this about our fallibility with respect to claims about Xs doesn't in itself entail changing our view as to whether Xs are really there, independently of us, etc. Coming to think we are more or less infallible about Xs can involve wildly upgrading our estimate of our epistemic powers, rather than downgrading our realism about Xs. So we shouldn't tie realism to fallibilism too tightly.
Weir's arguments here do go pretty quickly (too quickly to be likely to sway a Dummett or a Putnam, for example); but I won't pause over the details as in fact I rather agree with his interim conclusion:
I find myself in sympathy with Devitt in wishing to return to a traditional 'ontological' characterization of realism as mind-independent existence. (p. 22)
Or at least, I agree that realism about Xs should be construed as an ontological claim, not an epistemic or semantic claim. But Weir's version takes us back to those puzzles about how best to spell out 'mind-independent'. And here, it seems to me, he takes a wrong turn. For having just explained why he thinks that realism-as-fallibilism won't do, he now suggests that we can "effect a compromise" and proposes
a Devitt-style 'ontological' characterization of realism with respect to a given set of entities as constituted by a belief in their mind-independent existence, where mind-independence is, in turn, chararacterized in fallibilist terms à la Putnam and Dummett.
But will this do, even by Weir's own lights? Isn't this compromise package vulnerable to (some of) the same objections as pure realism-as-fallibilism? In particular, doesn't it again implausibly imply that inflating our estimate of ourselves and supposing we have the relevant kind of infallibility with regard to claims about Xs would entail thereby rejecting realism about Xs themselves?
I'm not sure how Weir would respond to that jab, nor how he would fix those variables left dangling in a schematic statement of mind-independence as fallibilism. Instead he goes off on another — and more promising — tack, noting that
Someone who holds to evidence-transcendent truth and affirms that Xs exist should not count as a realist about Xs if the affirmation of the existence of Xs, though sincere, should not be taken at face value or else should not be read in a straight representational fashion.
That's surely right: to be a realist about Xs involves affirming the existence of X without crossing your fingers as you say it, or proposing to 'decode' such an affirmation as in some way not being about what it at surface level seems to be about (or treating it as not in the business of representing how things are at all). Thus, to take Weir's example, the modal structuralist might take at least some arithmetical claims to be true in an evidence-transcending way: but that hardly makes her a realist about numbers if she parses the claims — including apparently existence-affirming claims like 'there is a prime number between 25 and 30' — as really claims about what happens in concretely realized structures across possible worlds. Or to go back to Berkeley, the good bishop might allow some claims about the physical world to true independently of our human ability to discover them to be so, but that hardly makes him a realist about physical things, given the decoding he offers for such claims when thinking with the learned.
OK, suppose we say — taking the core of Weir's line — that you are a realist about Xs if you affirm that there are Xs, where that is to be taken in a "straight representational fashion" and is to be "taken at face value" (not reconstrued, or decoded). You can immediately see why, quite trivially, Weir's philosophy of mathematics will count for him as anti-realist, given that he has announced that on his view mathematical talk is non-representational. But of course, all the work remains to be done in explaining what it is to mean something as representational and intend it to be taken at face value.
Though here's a concluding thought. We might suggest that it is a condition of talk of Xs being apt to be taken "at face value" that it involves continuing to respect enough everyday platitudes about the kind of things Xs are. And in some case — e.g. where X's are everyday things like sticks and stones — those platitudes will involve ideas of 'mind- independence' (the sticks and stones are the sort of thing that will still be there even if no one is seeing them, thinking of them, etc.). So taking talk of sticks and stones at face value will involve taking it as respecting the 'mind-independence' of such things. Which suggest that perhaps that realism about X's (meaning just representational face-value affirmation of the existence of Xs) will already bring with it as much 'mind-independence' as is appropriate to Xs — more or less independence , varying with the Xs in question. If that's right, we needn't build mind-independence into the general characterization of realism: it will just fall out for realism about Xs if and when appropriate.
Truth Through Proof, 3. §§1.I–1.II: Realisms
As we can see from our initial specification of his position, to get Weir's philosophy of mathematics to fly will involve accepting some substantial and potentially controversial claims in the philosophy of language and metaphysics. The first two chapters of TTP fill in some of the needed background. Weir starts by talking a bit about realism(s). Given that, in the Introduction at p. 6, he has already characterized himself as aiming for "an anti-realist … reading of mathematics", we should get clear about what kind of realism he is anti.
However, I didn't find the ensuing discussion altogether clear (is it perhaps extracted from something longer?). So in what follows, I'm reconstructing a little, but hopefully in a broadly sympathetic way, for I do at least want to end up pretty much where Weir does.
Traditional realisms, he says, "affirm the mind-independent existence of some sort of entity". But what does 'mind-independent' mean here? The problems are immediate. For a start, which kinds of minds count? On the one hand, if it's just finite sublunary minds, then Berkeley comes out a realist, which isn't what we want (Weir himself contrasts realism with idealism). On the other hand — Weir might have noted — if we agree with Berkeley and count God as among the minds, then any traditional theist who believes that the physical world is dependent for its existence on God would ipso facto count as an non-realist about sticks and stones, which is also surely not what we want. Then there are other problems with the traditional formulation: on a crude reading, it seems to define away the very possibility of being a realist about minds.
Let's put those worries on hold just for a moment, and turn to consider the modern theme that realism should instead best be characterized in epistemic terms. Thus Dummett (quoted by Weir): 'Realism I characterise as the belief that statements … possess an objective truth value, independently of our means of knowing it.' Of course, others such as Devitt have emphatically insisted contra Dummett that realism about Xs, properly understood, is an ontological doctrine about what there is, and is not to be confused with any epistemic or semantic doctrine. Where does Weir stand on this?
Well, he spends some time discussing the idea that realism is a species of fallibilism. We can present this sort of realism about a region of discourse R schematically as saying
For every (or some?) R-sentence s, it is possible (what kind of possibility?) for speakers (which speakers? even in optimal conditions?) to believe s though it is not true, or disbelieve s though it not false.
There are four dimensions along which versions of realism-as-fallibilism can vary, corresponding to the four queries. And Weir doesn't hold out much hope that there is any way of setting the variables to give us a thesis which is substantive enough to be interesting but also sufficiently captures what a realist is after. He offers a number of considerations. Embroidering a bit, we could perhaps put one of them like this. Suppose we keep fixed our view about the nature of Xs but change our mind about the quality of our epistemic access to Xs. Suppose we become very optimistic — perhaps implausibly over-optimistic — and now think that, at least when we are optimally placed and exercising our cognitive faculties in the optimal way, there are (enough) claims about Xs which (in the relevant sense of 'possible') it is not possible for us to go wrong about. Then, the thought goes, surely changing our view like this about our fallibility with respect to claims about Xs doesn't in itself entail changing our view as to whether Xs are really there, independently of us, etc. Coming to think we are more or less infallible about Xs can involve wildly upgrading our estimate of our epistemic powers, rather than downgrading our realism about Xs. So we shouldn't tie realism to fallibilism too tightly.
Weir's arguments here do go pretty quickly (too quickly to be likely to sway a Dummett or a Putnam, for example); but I won't pause over the details as in fact I rather agree with his interim conclusion:
I find myself in sympathy with Devitt in wishing to return to a traditional 'ontological' characterization of realism as mind-independent existence. (p. 22)
Or at least, I agree that realism about Xs should be construed as an ontological claim, not an epistemic or semantic claim. But Weir's version takes us back to those puzzles about how best to spell out 'mind-independent'. And here, it seems to me, he takes a wrong turn. For having just explained why he thinks that realism-as-fallibilism won't do, he now suggests that we can "effect a compromise" and proposes
a Devitt-style 'ontological' characterization of realism with respect to a given set of entities as constituted by a belief in their mind-independent existence, where mind-independence is, in turn, chararacterized in fallibilist terms à la Putnam and Dummett.
But will this do, even by Weir's own lights? Isn't this compromise package vulnerable to (some of) the same objections as pure realism-as-fallibilism? In particular, doesn't it again implausibly imply that inflating our estimate of ourselves and supposing we have the relevant kind of infallibility with regard to claims about Xs would entail thereby rejecting realism about Xs themselves?
I'm not sure how Weir would respond to that jab, nor how he would fix those variables left dangling in a schematic statement of mind-independence as fallibilism. Instead he goes off on another — and more promising — tack, noting that
Someone who holds to evidence-transcendent truth and affirms that Xs exist should not count as a realist about Xs if the affirmation of the existence of Xs, though sincere, should not be taken at face value or else should not be read in a straight representational fashion.
That's surely right: to be a realist about Xs involves affirming the existence of X without crossing your fingers as you say it, or proposing to 'decode' such an affirmation as in some way not being about what it at surface level seems to be about (or treating it as not in the business of representing how things are at all). Thus, to take Weir's example, the modal structuralist might take at least some arithmetical claims to be true in an evidence-transcending way: but that hardly makes her a realist about numbers if she parses the claims — including apparently existence-affirming claims like 'there is a prime number between 25 and 30' — as really claims about what happens in concretely realized structures across possible worlds. Or to go back to Berkeley, the good bishop might allow some claims about the physical world to true independently of our human ability to discover them to be so, but that hardly makes him a realist about physical things, given the decoding he offers for such claims when thinking with the learned.
OK, suppose we say — taking the core of Weir's line — that you are a realist about Xs if you affirm that there are Xs, where that is to be taken in a "straight representational fashion" and is to be "taken at face value" (not reconstrued, or decoded). You can immediately see why, quite trivially, Weir's philosophy of mathematics will count for him as anti-realist, given that he has announced that on his view mathematical talk is non-representational. But of course, all the work remains to be done in explaining what it is to mean something as representational and intend it to be taken at face value.
Though here's a concluding thought. We might suggest that it is a condition of talk of Xs being apt to be taken "at face value" that it involves continuing to respect enough everyday platitudes about the kind of things Xs are. And in some case — e.g. where X's are everyday things like sticks and stones — those platitudes will involve ideas of 'mind- independence' (the sticks and stones are the sort of thing that will still be there even if no one is seeing them, thinking of them, etc.). So taking talk of sticks and stones at face value will involve taking it as respecting the 'mind-independence' of such things. Which suggest that perhaps that realism about X's (meaning just representational face-value affirmation of the existence of Xs) will already bring with it as much 'mind-independence' as is appropriate to Xs — more or less independence , varying with the Xs in question. If that's right, we needn't build mind-independence into the characterization of realism (it will just fall out when appropriate), and Weir's fussing about associated ideas of fallibilism was indeed a rather unnecessary detour.
January 4, 2011
Cambridge Conference on the Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics
The fourth in a series of now annual conferences takes place in Cambridge over the weekend of 22nd–23rd January 2011. The previous conferences have been excellent fun, so why not come along? Here is the line-up for this year's event.
Keynote speakers:
Graham Priest (Melbourne/CUNY/St. Andrews): Dialetheism, Concepts, and the World
Rosanna Keefe (Sheffield): Modelling vagueness: what can we ignore?
Graduate papers:
Sharon Berry (Harvard): Solving the Access Problem for the Nominalist
James Collin (Edinburgh): Exists
Dmitri Gallow (Michigan): Frege Defining Functions
Jon Litland (Harvard): The Barcan Formulae for Determinacy
Jonathan Payne (Sheffield): Syntactic Priority Generalised
Giacomo Turbanti (Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa): Modality in Brandom's Semantics
If you want to come along you can register via the conference website. (Note that this is a fix-your-own-Saturday-night-accommodation-with-friends affair, which keeps registration very cheap.)
January 2, 2011
These you have loved …
I am as bad as the rest of you. I almost daily visit someone's website or blog, read their words of wisdom, download papers, talks, or overhead slides, and learn a huge amount this way. Yet I almost never post a comment or drop an e-mail to say "thanks". Which doesn't at all reflect how genuinely appreciative I am, or acknowledge what a difference all this has made to my logical life.
So I can hardly feel aggrieved when, in its turn, this blog gets about 10,000 visitors a month (or almost 30,000, counting repeat visits), some of the papers and handouts posted here have been downloaded thousands of times, and yet I get about one email every three months. So it is good to know that the number of visits steadily drifts upwards, and stuff indeed gets read.
But it is surprising too to discover from last year's summary stats what gets picked up. For example, leaving aside stuff related to my logic book and the much-downloaded Gödel Without Tears series (yes, I'll be finishing the updates on that over the coming weeks), who would have guessed that over 3000 people would have downloaded the handout on Galois connections I dashed off for some grad students. It was very nice to see too that 750 people downloaded my two page handout on Kleene's very pretty proof of the first incompleteness theorem, and a similar number a longer piece on Kreisel's squeezing argument a later version of which has now been published in Analysis. As to other webpages, the LaTeX for Logicians section gets visited quite a bit in a steady way, as one might have expected (though I've not been doing much to maintain them recently — I wonder if there is anyone out there who would sooner or later like to pick up the baton and run with it?). And I was amused to see that the page I dashed off in the first flush of excitement as a proud owner of an iPad got visited over 8000 times in just five months (though I guess I should update that page: I'd now stress some limitations as well as the things it does well …).
Anyway, as I said, it is nice to know I'm not just talking to myself here! So very best wishes for 2011 to all of you out there.