What Is Real?: The Unfinished Quest for the Meaning of Quantum Physics
Rate it:
Open Preview
2%
Flag icon
Quantum physics works, but ignoring what it tells us about reality means papering over a hole in our understanding of the world—and ignoring a larger story about science as a human process. Specifically, it ignores a story about failure: a failure to think across disciplines, a failure to insulate scientific pursuits from the corrupting influence of big money and military contracts, and a failure to live up to the ideals of the scientific method.
6%
Flag icon
Einstein had read Mach’s History of Mechanics as a student and was deeply impressed with his criticism of the Newtonian ideas of absolute space and time. “This book exercised a profound influence on me,” he wrote decades later. Taking Mach’s ideas about eliminating extraneous unobservable entities to heart, Einstein had tackled the problem of the aether, finding it to be an unnecessary hypothesis in special relativity. And, better still, special relativity also consigned to oblivion the absolute space and time that Mach had so despised.
6%
Flag icon
And the name “relativity” itself, which suggests a rejection of absolutes, was introduced by the physicist Max Planck, not Einstein—Einstein disliked the name “relativity” precisely because it connoted a kind of relativism. He preferred the name “invariant theory,” which conjures up a very different set of associations.
6%
Flag icon
While Mach believed that physics was merely about organizing perceptions of the world, to Einstein, physics was about the world itself. “Science,” he said, “has the sole purpose of determining what is.”
9%
Flag icon
Heisenberg started thinking about what would happen if you tried to measure the position of a single particle, like an electron, to very high precision. He realized that you could do this the same way you’d look for a lost wallet in a dark field: shine a flashlight around until you’ve found what you’re looking for. An ordinary flashlight wouldn’t work for an electron, though—the wavelength of visible light is far too large for that. But Heisenberg knew you could find an electron using higher-energy light, with a shorter wavelength: gamma rays. Shine a gamma-ray flashlight around the room, and ...more
13%
Flag icon
Entanglement, Schrödinger found, is pervasive in quantum physics. When any two subatomic particles collide, they almost always become entangled. When a group of objects forms some larger object, like subatomic particles in an atom or atoms in a molecule, they become entangled. In fact, nearly any interaction between any particles would cause them to become entangled, sharing a single wave function in the same way as the particles in the EPR thought experiment.
15%
Flag icon
A typical atomic nucleus is 100,000 times smaller than the surrounding electron cloud, which is itself a million times smaller than the width of a human hair. At such close quarters, the electrical repulsion between the protons in the nucleus, left unchecked, would send them flying off at nearly the speed of light. Instead, atomic nuclei are held together by an even stronger force, unimaginatively dubbed the “strong nuclear force.” The strong force binds together the protons and neutrons in atomic nuclei. Neutrons are electrically neutral—hence the name—but they feel the strong force just like ...more
22%
Flag icon
Bohm accounted for the strange results of the double-slit experiment by doing exactly what the Copenhagen interpretation said was impossible: he gave a detailed account of what happens in the quantum world whether or not anyone is looking. Photons, according to Bohm, are particles surfing on waves. While a particle can only pass through one slit, its pilot wave passes through both and interferes with itself. That self-interference, in turn, affects the motion of the particle, because it is guided by the wave. The wave pushes the particle onto a path ensuring the appearance of an interference ...more
29%
Flag icon
Bryce DeWitt, Wheeler’s colleague, fellow quantum cosmologist, and co-organizer of the Chapel Hill quantum gravity conference, was skeptical of Everett’s thesis at first. “I am afraid that it is precisely at the most crucial point in Everett’s argument where many people, including myself, will be unable to swallow your implication.… What I am not prepared to accept” is the branching of worlds required by Everett’s theory, wrote DeWitt to Wheeler. “I can testify to this from personal introspection, as can you. I simply do not branch.” Wheeler passed DeWitt’s reply on to Everett; in his reply, ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
32%
Flag icon
And because Bohm’s theory is contextual, it evades all of the proofs that supposedly rule it out. “What is proved by impossibility proofs,” concluded Bell, “is lack of imagination.”
36%
Flag icon
The logical positivists were understandably opposed to philosophical castles in the sky and the tortuous prose they were often defended with. But the logical positivists weren’t merely against metaphysics—they believed they could actually dismiss metaphysical claims as meaningless. Meaning, they held, was a matter of verification: knowing what a statement means is equivalent to knowing how to verify it using your senses. According to the positivists, when you say “it’s hotter outside than it is in here,” you really mean “if you go outside, you will feel hotter than you do in here.” The ...more
41%
Flag icon
The philosophers had successfully overthrown positivism and had a good understanding of the mathematical intricacies of quantum physics—but the physicists were still blinkered, walled off from philosophy and the developments there. They had no idea any of this had happened. While Einstein and Bohr’s generation was widely schooled in philosophy, the push toward specialization after World War II had taken its toll on the liberal arts education of the new crop of physicists. Academic departments had become Balkanized as they had grown in the postwar boom, and physicists, busy with enormous grants ...more
47%
Flag icon
There were only a handful of journals that would accept papers on quantum foundations, among them Foundations of Physics, where Zeh’s paper had finally ended up. To solve this problem, the quantum underground founded a new ersatz “journal” called Epistemological Letters. Billing itself as a permanent written symposium on “hidden variables and quantum uncertainty,” this samizdat was hand-typed, published by mimeograph, and overseen by an informal collection of editors, including Shimony.
49%
Flag icon
Feynman himself had explained Bell’s theorem during his keynote speech at an MIT conference in 1981 (though strangely he did not actually mention Bell himself in the course of doing so). The conference was on a seemingly unrelated subject—the physics of computation—yet Feynman showed that Bell’s theorem held the answer to a crucial question in this field. “Can physics be simulated by a universal computer?” Feynman asked the conference. “[The] physical world is quantum mechanical, and therefore the proper problem is the simulation of quantum physics—which is what I really want to talk about,” ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
52%
Flag icon
if subatomic particles can behave so strangely and we and the objects in our everyday lives are composed of such particles, why don’t we see such strange behavior on a regular basis? According to spontaneous-collapse theory, the answer lies in two key facts: entanglement and the vast number of particles that comprise the objects of our everyday experience. Though a single-particle wave function might not collapse on average until a billion years have passed, the solid objects of our everyday lives, like this book, are generally composed of at least 10 million billion billion individual ...more
53%
Flag icon
DeWitt’s article, “Quantum Mechanics and Reality,” did review several interpretations. But DeWitt made his own opinions quite clear. “The Copenhagen view promotes the impression that the collapse of the [wave function], and even the [wave function] itself, is all in the mind,” he wrote. “If this impression is correct, then what becomes of reality? How can one treat so cavalierly the objective world that obviously exists all around us?” When dealing with a system in a quantum superposition, like Schrödinger’s cat, DeWitt said most physicists “conceive the [measurement device] to have entered a ...more
54%
Flag icon
General relativity didn’t merely deal with abstruse situations—it was also written in abstruse mathematics. The theory is very mathematically complex, far more so than quantum mechanics. Einstein famously had to enlist the help of a mathematician friend, Marcel Grossman, just to learn the differential geometry necessary to formulate and understand his own theory. This combination of unfamiliar subject matter and obscure mathematics made it difficult to be sure of what the theory was saying and led many physicists to be suspicious of its conclusions.
55%
Flag icon
Several years later, in his seminal paper on quantum computing, Deutsch claimed that only the many-worlds interpretation could explain the fabulous increase in speed that quantum computers offered. “The Everett interpretation explains well how the [quantum] computer’s behaviour follows from its having delegated subtasks to copies of itself in other universes,” Deutsch wrote. “When the [quantum] computer succeeds in performing two processor-days of computation, how would the conventional interpretations explain the presence of the correct answer?Where was it computed?”
59%
Flag icon
Part of the problem is that there is no single “Copenhagen interpretation” and never really was. “The name ‘Copenhagen interpretation’ has gotten pretty slippery,” said Nina Emery, a philosopher of physics at Mt. Holyoke. “The semantic confusion makes it easy for physicists to avoid dealing with those flaws directly. For instance, when you push them on the idea that measurements cause collapse… they shift and start talking about some kind of Bohrian view or about the [mathematics of the theory]. And if you point out the issues with those views (e.g. who knows what the former is; and the latter ...more
63%
Flag icon
So many people today—and even professional scientists—seem to me like somebody who has seen thousands of trees but has never seen a forest. A knowledge of the historic and philosophical background gives that kind of independence from prejudices of his generation from which most scientists are suffering. This independence created by philosophical insight is—in my opinion—the mark of distinction between a mere artisan or specialist and a real seeker after truth. —Albert Einstein