Thought experiments in philosophy

Philosophers love thought experiments. Many of us deploy them as our version of the scientific method. They isolate some feature of our experience and evoke intuitions about it, and these revealed verdicts enable us to adjust relevant theories in light of what we find.


The method goes back to Plato, who, for example, has a character in The Republic challenge Socrates’s view of morality by appealing to the possibility of a ring that could make its bearer invisible, in order to demonstrate that people are most fundamentally self-interested.


Here are some of the other famous philosophical thought experiments:



Suppose there were a planet that was a duplicate of Earth in every way except that the chemical compound of the colorless, odorless drinkable stuff in its lakes and rivers was not H20 but something else, XYZ. Would XYZ be water? (Hilary Putnam)
Suppose you knew absolutely nothing about your social status, race, ethnicity, gender, basic life plan, or prospects. Under these conditions, what political conception would you choose to live under? (John Rawls)
Suppose you are alone in a room, where sheets of paper with strings of Chinese characters written on them are slipped in, and you are supposed to write different strings of Chinese characters on a different piece of paper according to an extremely detailed set of instructions, which you then slip out the door. It turns out you are fooling those outside the door into believing there is a Chinese speaker in the room answering their questions. Does this room — allegedly akin to a computer — understand Chinese? (John Searle)
Suppose we could transplant one half of your brain into each of the skulls of your identical siblings (whose own brains were destroyed). Each resulting person would wake up thinking he or she is you, with all psychological connections to you preserved. Which one would be you? (Derek Parfit)
Suppose a goddess designs a zygote, combining its atoms in such a way that it grows into a person (Ernie) who eventually judges it best to perform precisely the action the goddess designed him to perform at that moment in time. Does he perform this action freely? (Al Mele)
Suppose a team of brilliant neuroscientists has the ability to manipulate Plum into deciding to kill White by producing in him a strongly egoistic neural state just before he reasons about whether to do so, a state that determines he will decide to do so. Is he morally responsible for killing White? (Derk Pereboom)

There are many worries one might have about this general method. The cases aren’t sufficiently detailed, they yield conflicting intuitions, they generate framing effects, the intuitions garnered for use in the theory are culturally bound, and so on. But the worry I want to focus on instead is that sometimes we appeal to these science fiction cases too quickly when there are plenty of real life cases all around us that are potentially more fruitful.


“sometimes we appeal to these science fiction cases too quickly when there are plenty of real life cases all around us that are potentially more fruitful”.

Consider the last two thought experiments. They are both intended to get us to think ultimately about whether freedom and responsibility are really possible in a fully determined world, as each of the external manipulators dramatically brings to life different features of a deterministic world.


They are also, more importantly, meant to isolate the relevant features in a way that will yield clear intuitions on our part. Neither Ernie nor Plum acts freely or is morally responsible, obviously. And the precisely-drawn nature of the cases, and our clear-cut responses to them, are what is supposed to enable us to see more clearly how to make judgments of agency and responsibility about actual people in the messier real world.


But the very messiness of the real world should perhaps give us some pause about this method. Responsibility, for instance, has attached to it a whole range of emotions and practices; anger, gratitude, admiration, disdain, praise, punishment, reward, criticism, withdrawal of trust or warm feelings, and so on. These are deeply ingrained human emotions and practices, typically with a long evolutionary or cultural history.


Consequently, it is hard to see how we might theorize about responsibility in the first place without taking seriously these deeply ingrained responses. But the fact that our responses are so messy when it comes to many real-life people might just mean that responsibility is messy, that perhaps it can’t be made as precise as the thought-experimental method would have us believe.


Numerous real-life cases illustrate the point. None of us are ideal agents, but we may still achieve insight into the nature of agency by investigating the many different kinds of nonideal agents among us.


For example, what are we to think of the responsibility of people with clinical depression, Alzheimer’s disease, OCD, kleptomania, psychopathy, intellectual disabilities, Tourette syndrome, or those from horrifying or morally deprived childhoods? Many of us either know people with these backgrounds or conditions, or we are such people.


These agents tend to elicit in us a profound unease. We may feel, for instance, that only some of our responsibility emotions and practices are appropriate for them. Or we may feel that some of these agents deserve very different responses than others. Or we may feel that “there but for the grace of God” considerations suggest we extend our unease about their responsibility to those without such disorders and backgrounds.


In any event, thinking hard about these cases may reveal that our commitments and dispositions with respect to real life agents are surprisingly complex and informative, so much so that our intuitions about thought experiments that abstract away from real life details are misleading or irrelevant.


And a bonus of focusing on real-life cases is that we can get help on their crucial empirical details from various sciences employing the actual scientific method (e.g., psychology, biology, neurophysiology), which enriches our theorizing in interdisciplinary ways. And why shouldn’t we approach the matter in this way if our aim is to understand human agency and responsibility?


Philosophical thought experiments are lots of fun to design and think about. But they may obscure reality or prevent progress when too removed from our actual experience. Perhaps, then, we should be appealing far more often to the wide variety of fascinating and complex real life cases near to hand.


Featured image credit: The Death of Socrates, by Jacques-Louis David (1787). Public domain via Wikiart.


The post Thought experiments in philosophy appeared first on OUPblog.


 •  0 comments  •  flag
Share on Twitter
Published on April 26, 2015 00:30
No comments have been added yet.


Oxford University Press's Blog

Oxford University Press
Oxford University Press isn't a Goodreads Author (yet), but they do have a blog, so here are some recent posts imported from their feed.
Follow Oxford University Press's blog with rss.