Swinburne on the Perfect Goodness of God

In Chapter 11 of The Coherence of Theism (revised edition, hereafter: COT), Richard Swinburne argues (among other things) that the following sentence makes a coherent statement:



 (PG) There is a person who is perfectly good.



Perfect goodness is one of the divine attributes that theists use to define the word 'God'.  In order to show that the statement 'God exists' makes a coherent statement, Swinburne attempts to show that each of the divine attributes that are used to define the word 'God', and to clarify the meaning of the statement 'God exists', can be used to make coherent statements.  


Swinburne takes himself to have shown (in previous chapters of COT) that the following sentence makes a coherent statement:



(BOP) There is a person who is both omniscient and perfectly free.



Swinburne's method of showing a sentence to express a coherent statement is to show that some other statement which is known to be coherent entails the statement in question.  So, since Swinburne has previously argued that (BOP) makes a coherent statement, all he needs to do in Chapter 11 to show that (PG) makes a coherent statement, is to show that (BOP) entails (PG).



The following is an email exchange that I had recently with Richard Swinburne about a key argument in Chapter 11 of COT on this issue.



=======================






On 23/11/2012 21:19, Bradley Bowen
wrote:

Mr. Swinburne,

I have recently been studying Chapter
11 of your book The
Coherence of Theism
 (revised
edition), and have a question about your argument for the claim
that "it is logically necessary that an omniscient and perfectly
free being be perfectly good." (COT, p.188)

I have put your understanding of the
divine attribute of perfect goodness into a formal definition:

A person P is perfectly good if and only if (a) P is so
constituted that P always does the morally best action (when there is
one), and (b) P is so constituted that P does  no morally bad action.  (see COT, p.184)


I have also attempted to state your
argument (see COT, p.208) as follows:

(PFO1) An omniscient person O will know
of any action whether or not that action is morally good or morally bad, and
will know this because of O’s nature (i.e. O has the attribute of omniscience).


(PFO2) A perfectly free person F will
do those actions that F believes are morally good and avoid those actions that
F believes are morally bad, and will act this way because of F’s nature (i.e. F
has the attribute of perfect freedom).


(PFO3) It is logically possible for a
person to be both omniscient and perfectly free (at the same time).


Therefore:

(PFO4) Any person P who is both
omniscient and perfectly free (at the same time) will do those actions that are
morally good and avoid those actions that are morally bad, and will act this
way because of P’s nature (i.e. P has the attributes of omniscience and perfect
freedom).
 

There appears to be a disconnection
between the conclusion of this argument, which is in terms of doing actions
that are "morally good" and the definition of the divine attribute of
perfect goodness, which is in terms of doing the "morally best action
(when there is one)".  

How do you bridge the apparent logical
gap between the idea of doing "morally good" actions and doing
"the morally best" action?

Bradley Bowen

Kirkland, Washington

USA




=============================




Date: Tue, 27 Nov 2012
10:48:21 +0000


From: richard.swinburne

To: bbowen

Subject: Re: The Perfect Goodness of God

Dear Bradley,

 Thank you for
your email. What I wrote, and what you quote from me, is that a perfectly good
being ‘always does the morally best action’ (when there is one). I emphasize
the ‘when there is one’.
Sometimes among the actions open to such a being will be two equal best
actions, that is actions such that they are both better than any other action
open to that being and each is just as good as the other. That is a situation
with which we are often ourselves confronted. Some beings (including God, but
not including humans) may also have a choice among an infinite number of
actions, each of which is less good than some other action which he could do.
For example, God has a choice of how many solar systems to create; and on the
assumption that solar systems are good things, then the more of them the
better. So however many he creates, he could do better by creating more. In
that case, since it is not logically possible that such a being could do either
the best action or an equal best action, his perfect goodness would consist
simply in doing an action of the relevant kind (e.g. creating solar systems),
but it wouldn’t be the best or equal best action, but it would be a
good action. What you have labelled (PFO4) does follow from the premises which
you state; but I could have drawn the stronger and more complicated conclusion
that P will always do an action which is morally the best if there is one, or
an equal best action (when there
is no best) if there is one, or (if there is no best or equal best action)  a good
action. With best wishes

Richard Swinburne

=======================================

On 27/11/2012 19:39, Bradley Bowen
wrote:

Mr. Swinburne,



Thank you for your
response to my question about the argument for your claim that "it is
logically necessary that an omniscient and perfectly free being be perfectly good."
(COT, p.188)




Your key point: 



"What you have
labelled (PFO4) does follow from the premises which you state; but I could have
drawn the stronger and more complicated conclusion that P will always do an
action which is morally the best if there is one, or an equal best action (when
there is no best) if there is one, or (if there is no best or equal best
action) a good action."



To draw this stronger
conclusion, it seems to me that  stronger premises   would be
required, but I believe that you accept the stronger premises.



Here is one way to
strengthen the premise about the relationship of omniscience to perfect
goodness:



(PFO1') An omniscient
person O will know of any action whether or not that action is morally good or
morally bad,
 

and if an
action is morally good will know whether it
  is the morally best action among
available alternative morally
  good actions

and will know this
becauseof O’s nature (i.e. Ohas the attribute of omniscience).
 



A similar adjustment
could be made to the premise about the relationship between perfect freedom
and perfect goodness:



(PFO2') A
perfectly free person F will do those actions that F believes are morally good
and avoid those actions that F believes are morally bad,
  and F will do the action that F
believes is the morally best action among available alternative morally good
actions (when there is such an action),
  and will act this way because of F’s nature
(i.e. F has the attribute of perfect freedom).




Do you agree that the premises need to be strengthened in order to draw the
stronger conclusion?

Bradley Bowen

Kirkland, Washington

USA




=======================================




Date: Sat, 1 Dec 2012 12:34:29
+0000

From: richard.swinburne

To: bbowen

Subject: Re: The Perfect Goodness of God

Dear Bradley,

Unless I have missed something, your
(PFO1') is the same as your
(PFO1), and your (PFO2') is the
same as your (PFO2), and so they don’t constitute any strengthening of the
argument. You are however right that in order to get the ‘stronger and more
complicated conclusion’ which I described in my previous email, I do need a
stronger premise. The requisite premise is: a perfectly good being will – in so
far as it can – do what it believes is the best action, or (if it believes that
there is no best action but an equal best) do what it believes to be the equal
best action, or (if it believes that there is no best, and no equal best) will
do what it believes to be a good action. Given that premise and the premise about omniscience in the form that an omniscient being will have true beliefs about
which actions are best or equal best or good, and a premise that an omnipotent being will be able to do such actions, the
conclusion follows. With best wishes

Richard Swinburne

================================




From:Bradley Bowen  [image error]

Sent:Sat 12/08/12 7:46 PM

To:Richard Swinburne




Mr. Swinburne,

 

Thank
you for your suggested revision of my reformulation of an argument from p.208
of The Coherence of Theism (revised
ed.):

 

You are however
right that in order to get the ‘stronger and more complicated conclusion’ which
I described in my previous email, I do need a stronger premise. The requisite
premise is: a perfectly good being will – in so far as it can – do what it
believes is the best action, or (if it believes that there is no best action
but an equal best) do what it believes to be the equal best action, or (if it
believes that there is no best, and no equal best) will do what it believes to
be a good action.


 

Here is
how I would reformulate the argument, based on your suggested enhancement:





(PFO1*) An omniscient person O will know
of any action whether or not that action is a morally best action for
O or an equal best action for O, or just a good action (that is
neither a best nor an equal best action) for O, or a morally bad action
for O, and will know this because of O’s nature (i.e. because O has the
attribute of omniscience).


(PFO2*) A perfectly free person F will
do an action - in so far as it can - when F believes the action
is a morally best action for F 
or (if it believes that there is no best
action but an equal best) do what it believes to be an equal best
action for F, or (if it believes that there is no best, and no equal best) will
do what it believes to be a good action for F, and will not do any action it
believes to be a morally bad action for F, and will do these actions (and
refrain from morally bad actions) because of F's nature
 (i.e. becuase F has the attribute of
perfect freedom).


(PFO3*) It is logically possible for a
person to be both omniscient and perfectly free (at the same time).


Therefore:

(PFO4*) Any person P who is both
omniscient and perfectly free (at the same time) will do an action that is
a morally
best action for P
 or (if there is no best action but an
equal best) do an equal best action for P, or (if there is no best, and no
equal best) will do a good action for P, and will not do any action that
is a morally bad action for P, and will do these actions (and refrain from
morally bad actions) because of P's nature
 (i.e. becuase P has both the attribute
of omniscience and the attribute of perfect freedom).


I
believe the qualification "in so far as it can" in (PFO2*) falls out
because an omniscient being who judges and action to be a morally best action
for itself to perform is also judging that action to be one that is possible
for itself to perform, since ought implies can, and similar reasoning applies
to other moral categories (equal best, morally good, morally bad).



Do you
think this is a reasonable and enhanced reformulation of the argument on
p. 208 of The Coherence of Theism?

 

Bradley Bowen

Kirkland, Washington

USA




==================================








 •  0 comments  •  flag
Share on Twitter
Published on December 09, 2012 00:16
No comments have been added yet.


Keith Parsons's Blog

Keith Parsons
Keith Parsons isn't a Goodreads Author (yet), but they do have a blog, so here are some recent posts imported from their feed.
Follow Keith Parsons's blog with rss.