The Curious Incident of the Dog in the Night-Time
discussion
The Monty Hall problem.
date
newest »


Here are the three doors;
A B C
The car is behind door A.
There are three things that can happen here.
1. The players chooses door B. The presenter MUST open door C. In this s..."
I actually learned about this my Senior year in high school and this is the exact way he described it.

The first decision that you make is shown as having three branches. Note that the right hand branch is that "you choose a door with a goat behind it"
The problem states that Monty opens a door and shows us the goat and then asks us to decide to stay or trade.
Let's cover up that whole branch of the outcome matrix. and evaluate our second decision. That leaves us with 4 possible outcomes. In two you get a car, and in two you get a goat. There is no reason to trade (or to NOT trade) to better your odds. The key to understanding this problem is that you're making your second decision on a "pruned" outcome tree.
That's a concept that Chris admits that he has difficulty with. I know that the idea of choices based on subsequent information causes some people difficulty and since my belief is that there is no harm in swapping, I'll be glad to swap to mollify any of you that still have concerns.

At first you have a 1:3 chance of being right.
Then a door is KNOWINGLY chosen to be revealed. This is a door that has a goat behind it.
The odds of the door you originally chose to be right now become 1:2. Yes, the odds CHANGE even before you choose if you want to switch or stay. So there really is no difference if you stay or switch. Both doors now have a 50% chance of being the right door.

2) do you mean The second situation is not totally independent of the first situation?
3) I don't fancy myself being willfully ignorant so much as fancying myself a peacemaker by offering to swap. Understanding (like faith) is not something one can always command.
4) Can you explain why the pruned tree metaphor that I used is incorrect?

However as I said before... I'm willing to always swap. There is an infinity of information in the universe and I can't know or understand everything. So, since my intuition suggests that swapping will cause no HARM I'm willing to swap and admit that I don't understand everything.
On this (and how my catalytic converter works) I'm willing to remain willfully ignorant.

I guess that it's a bit like visualizing a tesseract. There are just some things one's brain is not equipped to do.


In this book, our protagonist admitted that he has trouble framing his analysis based on things that MIGHT happen. I guess that was my problem too.


Perception, understanding and belief are strange things. That image of a chalice that other's first perceive as two people kissing, that image of an old hag that other's first perceive as a young woman in an elegant feathered hat, those images that can be perceived as containing three dimensional images (see Magic Eye II: Now You See It)

It's difficult to covince someone to see something in a way that they do not. Sometimes one must just convince them to keep an open mind and keep trying.

Lets make it more ridiculous. There are 1,000,000,000 doors and one with a prize. You select one and and then all the other doors are opened and one remains shut. Do you change your pick now? You would be stupid not to because you had 1 out of a billion chances to be right, and there are therefore 999,999,999 chances out of a billion that the door being displayed is the one with the prize.
Take that back to the original question. 3 doors each having 33.33% chance of being the right one. No matter where the prize is there is definitely one door that you did not pick that is empty. So by showing you which the empty door is they have shown you where the prize is 2 out of 3 times.

At first you have a 1:3 chance of being right.
Then a door is KNOWINGLY chosen to be revealed. This is a door that has a goat behind it.
The odds of the door you originally..."
That is completely incorrect. Your odds never change, and in fact cannot change. They are simply showing you where the car by opening the door where it is not.


It is actually extremely interesting how many people do not stop and think this through. Monty Hall did this numerous times over the years and a surprising number of people did not change their pick.

If there was 10 cards on the table and you had to choose the one ace, and after you picked one card you could change it for the other 9 would you? Again 8 of those card are also for sure not the ace but one of them most likely is.
Reducing the number you start with make the odds less and less but they are still in your favour to change.

Taking the 3 doors, 2 goats and 1 car scenario, what if you do not change doors? I understand your odds are only 1/3 compared to 2/3, but what if on that occasion it was the 1/3 and the car was behind your original choice? After all, how many chances is anyone going to give you to win a car?



"Many readers refused to believe that switching is beneficial. After the Monty Hall problem appeared in Parade, approximately 10,000 readers, including nearly 1,000 with PhDs, wrote to the magazine claiming that vos Savant was wrong. (Tierney 1991) Even when given explanations, simulations, and formal mathematical proofs, many people still do not accept that switching is the best strategy."
It's counter-intuitive, to begin with, but when you actually play it out in your mind suddenly it seems obvious that you have to switch.

Game A: The Monty Hall problem, as described in the book, played by a person who always refuses to change his mind.
Game B: A game where a person can choose one of three doors, opens it immediately, and gets whatever is behind it. Only one of the three doors has a good prize.
It should be obvious, if you pause to think, that Game A is exactly the same as Game B. By choosing not to switch doors, you are choosing to play Game B, pick a door, get whatever is there. The next logical step is to see that a player of Game B only wins 1/3 times. So it should be quite clear that refusing to switch gives exactly a 1/3 chance.
----------------------------------
A wrinkle on the game, which could explain the human instinctive resistance to the solution. Imagine that I, Mr. Devious, offer my own version of the game. I let you pick a door. Then, IF you pick a loser, I immediately open it and shout "You lose, sucker!" IF, on the other hand, you picked a winner, I will then open one of the two doors that you didn't choose. I KNOW that both are losing doors. I then offer you the chance to change your mind. I know that you've never played this game before, you've never seen it before, and I just might trick you into changing your mind, because I want you to lose! In this case, obviously, changing your mind is a bad idea. And this kind of deviousness is how carnival games and three card monty games aim to cheat customers. Our natural distrust tells us to stick to our first choice. The mathematical discussion of probability above can look like further trickery. Any lack of clarity in explaining the exact terms of the game lead to further confusion, suspicion, and resistance. So it's no surprise that even clever people don't readily accept the correct answer. In describing the rules, not enough emphasis is placed on the fact that Monty Hall is consistently compelled to reveal a losing door, and that he does not actively try to cheat or trick the player. Understanding of human motives tends to trump mathematical analysis.
The book, however, is great, and I don't expect Christopher to be so exacting, as he doesn't really understand the very different terms by which other people would approach this problem.

Thanks in advance! :D


If I understand you correctly, yes that is exactly right.



im doing my IB (international baccalaureat) maths higher level coursework about this problem.
i have understood and managed to explain the problem and it is always better to switch.
now i have to questions to make:
1) can anyone help me explain the problem using conditional probability. Cus for tme the problem is so straight forward that i cant see where/how i can use conditional probability.
2) how can i apply the problem/its maths to a day to day basis?
thanks

2) how can i apply the problem/its maths to a day to day basis?
"
I'm not sure that you can apply the lesson of this problem to day to day life. One reason that it's a challenging problem to many people is that it runs counter to our daily experience, thus the intuitive response to the problem is wrong.
In this case, the game operator is constrained by the rules in such a way that he must reveal information that is valuable to us. He's not a competitor, he's an automaton, and the rules of the game are our collaborator.
-----------------------------
In a general sense the lessons we can learn are:
1) Know the "rules of the game." That is, know what constraints exist, and how they determine others' behavior.
2) Always be attentive to the behavior of others who have knowledge that we don't have. It may reveal something.
3) Exploit any information gathered from steps one and two, to the greatest possible advantage.
-------------------------------------------
Now, I'm not sure if I said this before, but I'll risk repetition. The reason that this problem does not reflect ordinary daily conditions is the special way the game was contrived. Imagine, instead, a more ordinary human style experience:
-You go to a carnival. A carny is running a game which appears similar to the game we've analyzed here (but the rules governing the carny are not the same). For $1 you can choose one of three boxes. One of the boxes has a prize of $2 in it, the others have discarded banana peels. You choose any box you like, and win whatever is in it.
-In this one time experience, having never played the game before, you choose box 'C.' The carny opens box 'B,' which contains banana peels, then offers you the opportunity to change your mind. Should you? No, of course not.
-Why not? Because the carny is unconstrained. He's never obligated to show you the contents of a box, he's never obligated to let you change your mind, he's just doing it now. Or at least, you have no knowledge of any rule that forces him to let you change your mind.
-What does game theory dictate that the carny should do? Well, if you're wrong on your first choice, he should open your choice immediately and not offer you a chance to change your mind. Haha sucker! But if you're right in your first choice, he should always give you a chance to change your mind, and to give you the impression that he's helping you out, he should always show you one of the other boxes, which contains banana peels. If you never change your mind, this practice doesn't hurt him... you're only going to win this game, at most, 1/3 times. But if you sometimes change your mind, then the carny improves his chances/expected profit.
-With this in mind, game theory dictates your choice. Never change your mind. But then, game theory also dictates your earlier choice. You should previously have chosen not to play this game at all, as it has guaranteed negative expectation.
This is the intuitive thinking which subconsciously dominates in most people's minds, which is why they stubbornly refuse to understand the Monty Hall problem... that, plus the people who present the problem rarely give adequate emphasis to the rules that absolutely dictate that the game operator must always give away information! Then they scoff when mere mortals bring their real world understanding into the game and fail to solve the purely mathematical problem which is disguised as a carnival game.


Looks like Stephen is gone, I'm hoping that means you all managed to convince him! I mean if you don't understand the Monty Hall problem, there are plenty of people willing to teach you, if you open your ears and your mind. Just don't decide Monty Hall is wrong because you don't get it.



Watch the link in post 13 and see if you still feel that way. That's the argument that convinced me. But then again, we all approach understanding these things differently.

Because there is a 2/3 (~66.67%) chance you'll get the car if you switch, not 50%.
This has all been discussed already but I'll make an attempt to make it simple:
If the door you pick originally is a goat and you switch, then you win a car because the other door has to be a car.
There is a 2/3 chance of picking a goat, so if you switch every time after the host shows you the goat, then you have a 2/3 chance of winning a car.
Some people prefer to view it this way:
You will lose when you switch only if you originally pick a car, which happens 1/3 of the time. Therefore, you win a car 2/3 of the time if you switch.
I hope that made sense.
Remember, this is all contingent upon the constraints and rules of the aforementioned problem.

If you buy a lottery ticket, you might win. That doesn't mean you have a 50% chance of winning. The fact that there are two possible outcomes does not mean that they are equally probable.


To take an extreme example: There are two rooms, there is a goat in one, and there is a car in the other. You are SURE that one of them IS a goat, and one of them IS a car. Now, your best friend peeks into the room and shouts at you "THE CAR IS IN ROOM B!!!!"
Again, you are sure that one is a goat, and one is a car, but the odds are not 50% each, because you've been given information to guide your choice.
The rules of the Monty Hall problem force the emcee to reveal information, and that's the key to the solution.
As has been said before in this thread, if you take a shuffled deck of cards, and your job is to guess which one is the queen of spades, imagine this scenario: You pick at random, and before I reveal your choice, I look through the remaining deck, throw 50 of the cards in the trash can, and say "none of those were the queen of spades!" I even show them to you to assure you that I'm not cheating. Now you have to choose between your first choice, or the one remaining card that I didn't throw in the trash.
You know that one IS a queen of spades, and one ISN'T, but the odds are no longer 50/50 from the point of view of a person who has been given this extra information.
-----------------------------
Final, most extreme example: There are two rooms, one with a car, one with a goat. You have to choose one and accept the prize. The doors are OPEN and you can SEE the car! Are the odds still 50/50 when you make your choice?

So that's it, I don't want to talk about this anymore, so i'm leaving.


You pick Goat A, he shows you Goat B, you change and get the car.
You pick Goat B, he shows you Goat A, you change and get the car.
You pick the car, he shows you a goat, you change and get other goat.
You get car 2 out of 3 times by switching.

On some levels that's as fascinating as the original conundrum.


im doing my IB (international baccalaureat) maths higher level coursework about this problem. ...
can anyone help me explain the problem using conditional probability.
..."
You can use conditional probability in the following way.
Suppose you choose box A. At this point B and C have a combined probability of 2/3 of containing a car.
If the host opens B then B does not contain a car.
The probability of C containing a car at this second point, i.e. conditional on the fact that B does not contain a car, is the same as the prior possibility of B or C containing the car. Hence prob. of C = 2/3, which is better than sticking with A.
all discussions on this book
|
post a new topic
The Curious Incident of the Dog in the Night-Time (other topics)
Books mentioned in this topic
Magic Eye II: Now You See It (other topics)The Curious Incident of the Dog in the Night-Time (other topics)
The columnist actually WAS wrong. There is NO benefit to changing the door you select. What this problem entails is that we have subsequent information. The odds of either door having the car are 50 50 once we KNOW that one of the doors had a goat. (Despite the diagrams in the book)
On the other hand, our protagonist has admitted that he has trouble with subjunctive/conditional logic. That is he has trouble framing his analysis based on things that MIGHT happen. So it's understandable that he can't see WHY his answer is not correct.
[I've since been convinced that my initial opinion was wrong. Read on for more details if you like. But keep an open mind.]