From Eternity to Here
Rate it:
Open Preview
Read between November 20, 2020 - March 27, 2022
63%
Flag icon
The weirdest thing about the idea that the space of states changes with time is that it requires an external time parameter—a concept of “time” that lives outside the actual universe, and through which the universe evolves. Ordinarily, we think of time as part of the universe—a coordinate on spacetime, measured by various sorts of predictably repetitive clocks. The question “What time is it?” is answered by reference to things going on within the universe—that is to say, to features of the state the universe is currently in. (“The little hand is on the three, and the big hand is on the ...more
63%
Flag icon
So for the space of states to change with time, we would have to posit a notion of time that is not merely measured by features of the state of the universe, but exists outside the universe as we conventionally understand it. Then it would make sense to say, “When this external time parameter was equal to a certain value, the space of states of the universe was relatively small, and when it had progressed to some other value the space of states had grown larger.”
63%
Flag icon
IRREVERSIBLE MOTIONS
64%
Flag icon
The laws of physics as we know them—putting aside the important question of wave function collapses in quantum mechanics—seem to be reversible. But we don’t know the final laws of physics; all we have are very good approximations. Is it conceivable that the real laws of physics are fundamentally irreversible, and that explains the arrow of time?
64%
Flag icon
To “explain” the arrow of time means to come up with a set of laws of physics, and an “initial” state of the universe, so that we naturally (without fine-tuning) witness a change in entropy over time of the sort we observe around us. In particular, if we simply assume that the initial conditions have low entropy, there is nothing to be explained—the entropy will tend to go up, in accordance with Boltzmann, and we’re done. In that case there’s simply no need to posit irreversible laws of physics; the reversible ones are up to the task. But the problem is that such a low-entropy boundary ...more
64%
Flag icon
Think carefully about what would have to happen for this scenario to work. The universe, for whatever reason, finds itself in a randomly chosen high-entropy state, which looks like empty de Sitter space. Now our postulated irreversible laws of physics act on that state to decrease the entropy. The result—if all this is to have any chance of working out—should be the history of our actual universe, just reversed in time compared to how we traditionally think about it. In other words: Out of the initial emptiness, some photons miraculously focus on a point in space to create a white hole. That ...more
64%
Flag icon
But the hypothesis we’re currently considering is very different: It says that an evolution of this form would happen for almost any high-entropy state of empty de Sitter space. That’s a lot to ask of some laws of physics. It’s one thing to imagine entropy going down as a result of irreversible laws, but it’s another thing entirely to imagine it going down in precisely the right way to produce a time-reversed history of our universe.
64%
Flag icon
Even though there are relatively few microstates corresponding to each low-entropy macrostate, there are a lot more individual low-entropy macrostates than there are high-entropy ones. (More formally, each low-entropy state contains more information than a high-entropy one.)
64%
Flag icon
This is not an airtight argument, but it seems likely that we will have to look somewhere else for an explanation of the arrow of time in the real world.
64%
Flag icon
A SPECIAL BEGINNING
64%
Flag icon
A dynamical law demonstrates its validity over and over again; at every moment, the law takes the current state and evolves it into the next state. But the boundary condition is just imposed once and for all; its nature is more like an empirical fact about the universe than an additional law of physics. There isn’t any substantive distinction between the statements “the early universe had a low entropy” and “it is a law of physics that the early universe had a low entropy” (unless we imagine that there are many universes, all with the same boundary condition).275 Be that as it may, it’s ...more
64%
Flag icon
A SYMMETRIC UNIVERSE
65%
Flag icon
We don’t know why entropy was low near the Big Bang, but it was; therefore, the fact that we don’t know why the entropy should be low near a Big Crunch is not a sufficient reason to discard the possibility. Indeed, without introducing time asymmetry by hand, it stands to reason that whatever unknown principle of physics enforces the low entropy at the Bang could also do so at the Crunch.
65%
Flag icon
If you think you have some natural explanation for why the early universe had such a low entropy, but you claim not to invoke any explicit violations of time-reversal symmetry, why shouldn’t the late universe look the same way? This thought experiment drives home just how puzzling the low-entropy configuration of the Big Bang really is.
65%
Flag icon
The smart money these days is that the universe won’t actually re-collapse. The universe is accelerating; if the dark energy is an absolutely constant vacuum energy (which is the most straightforward possibility), the acceleration will continue forever. We don’t know enough to say for sure, but it’s most likely that our future is absolutely unlike our past. Which, again, places the unusual circumstances surrounding the Big Bang front and center as a puzzle we would like to solve.
65%
Flag icon
BEFORE THE B...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
65%
Flag icon
General relativity doesn’t predict that space and time didn’t exist before the Big Bang; it predicts that the curvature of spacetime in the very early universe became so large that general relativity itself ceases to be reliable. Quantum gravity, which we can happily ignore when we’re talking about the curvature of spacetime in the relatively placid context of the contemporary universe, absolutely must be taken into account. And, sadly, we don’t understand quantum gravity well enough to say for sure what actually happens at very early times. It might very well be true that space and time “come ...more
65%
Flag icon
AN ARROW FOR ALL TIME
66%
Flag icon
A MIDDLE HYPOTHESIS
66%
Flag icon
BABY UNIVERSES
66%
Flag icon
The question that any modern theory of cosmology must therefore answer is: Why don’t we live in de Sitter space? It has a high entropy, it lasts forever, and the curvature of spacetime induces a small but nonzero temperature. De Sitter space is empty apart from the thin background of thermal radiation, so for the most part it is completely inhospitable to life; there is no arrow of time, since it’s in thermal equilibrium. There will be thermal fluctuations, just as we would expect in a sealed box of gas in a Newtonian spacetime. Such fluctuations can give rise to Boltzmann brains, or entire ...more
66%
Flag icon
If de Sitter space gives birth to a continuous stream of baby universes, each of which starts with a low entropy and expands into a high-entropy de Sitter phase of its own, we could have a natural mechanism for creating more and more entropy in the universe.
66%
Flag icon
They suggested that spacetime could not only bend and stretch, as in ordinary classical general relativity, but also split into multiple pieces. In particular, a tiny bit of space could branch off from a larger universe and go its own way. The separate bit of space is, naturally, known as a baby universe. (In contrast to the “pocket universes” mentioned in the last chapter, which remained connected to the background spacetime.)
66%
Flag icon
What we see is a simultaneous fluctuation of the inflaton field, creating a bubble of false vacuum, and of space itself, creating a region that pinches off from the rest of the universe. The tiny throat that connects the two is a wormhole, as we discussed way back in Chapter Six. But this wormhole is unstable and will quickly collapse to nothing, leaving us with two disconnected spacetimes: the original parent universe and the tiny baby. Now we have a baby universe, dominated by false vacuum energy, all set up to undergo inflation and expand to a huge size. If the properties of the false ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
67%
Flag icon
A RESTLESS MULTIVERSE
67%
Flag icon
What we’ve done is given the universe a way that it can increase its entropy without limit. In a de Sitter universe, space grows without bound, but the part of space that is visible to any one observer remains finite, and has a finite entropy—the area of the cosmological horizon. Within that space, the fields fluctuate at a fixed temperature that never changes. It’s an equilibrium configuration, with every process occurring equally as often as its time-reverse. Once baby universes are added to the game, the system is no longer in equilibrium, for the simple reason that there is no such thing ...more
67%
Flag icon
That’s the trick: allowing entropy to continue to rise in both directions of time, even though it started out large to begin with. There isn’t any state we could possibly have chosen that would have prevented this kind of evolution from happening. An arrow of time is inevitable.
68%
Flag icon
BRINGING IT HOME
68%
Flag icon
The nice thing about a multiverse based on de Sitter space and baby universes is that it avoids all of the standard pitfalls that beset many approaches to the arrow of time: It treats the past and future on an equal footing, doesn’t invoke irreversibility at the level of fundamental dynamics, and never assumes an ad hoc low-entropy state for the universe at any moment in time. It serves as a demonstration that such an explanation is at least conceivable, even if we aren’t yet able to judge whether this particular one is sensible, much less part of the ultimately correct answer. There’s every ...more
68%
Flag icon
16
68%
Flag icon
EPILOGUE
68%
Flag icon
What happens here happens everywhere—as Richard Feynman put it, “The entire universe is in a glass of wine, if we look at it closely enough.”
68%
Flag icon
WHAT’S THE ANSWER?
68%
Flag icon
Our universe isn’t a fluctuation around an equilibrium background, or it would look very different. And it doesn’t seem likely that the fundamental laws of physics are irreversible at a microscopic level—or, if they are, it’s very hard to see how that could actually account for the evolution of entropy and complexity we observe in our universe. A boundary condition stuck at the beginning of time is impossible to rule out, but also seems to be avoiding the question more than answering it. It may ultimately be the best we can do, but I strongly suspect that the low entropy of our early universe ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
69%
Flag icon
There is one other approach lurking in the background, which we occasionally acknowledged but never granted our undivided attention: the idea that “time” itself is simply an approximation that is occasionally useful, including in our local universe, but doesn’t have any fundamental meaning. This is a perfectly legitimate possibility. Lessons from the holographic principle, as well as a general feeling that the underlying ingredients of a quantum mechanical theory may appear very different from what shows up in the classical regime, make it quite reasonable to imagine that time might be an ...more
69%
Flag icon
THE EMPIRICAL CIRCLE
69%
Flag icon
Scientists are fiercely proud of the empirical nature of what they do. Scientific theories do not become accepted because they are logical or beautiful, or fulfill some philosophical goal cherished by the scientist. Those might be good reasons why a theory is proposed—but being accepted is a much higher standard. Scientific theories must, at the end of the day, fit the data. No matter how intrinsically compelling a theory might be, if it fails to fit the data, it’s a curiosity, not an achievement.
69%
Flag icon
THE MULTIVERSE IS NOT A THEORY
69%
Flag icon
The correct way to think about the multiverse is as a prediction . The theory—such as it is, in its current underdeveloped state—is the marriage of the principles behind quantum field theory to our basic understanding of how curved spacetime works. Starting from those inputs, we don’t simply theorize that the universe could have undergone an early period of superfast acceleration; we predict that inflation should occur, if a quantum inflaton field with the right properties finds itself in the right state. Likewise, we don’t simply say, “Wouldn’t it be cool if there were an infinite number of ...more
69%
Flag icon
THE SEARCH FOR MEANING IN A PREPOSTEROUS UNIVERSE
70%
Flag icon
We don’t know exactly what happened 14 billion years ago, but there’s no reason whatsoever to doubt that we will eventually figure it out.
70%
Flag icon
NEXT STEPS
70%
Flag icon
Predicting the future isn’t easy. (Curse the absence of a low-entropy future boundary condition!) But the pieces are assembled for science to take dramatic steps toward answering the ancient questions we have about the past and the future. It’s time we understood our place within eternity.
70%
Flag icon
APPENDIX:
70%
Flag icon
MATH
70%
Flag icon
EXPONENTIALS
70%
Flag icon
BIG NUMBERS
71%
Flag icon
LOGARITHMS
71%
Flag icon
NOTES
83%
Flag icon
BIBLIOGRAPHY