Noise: A Flaw in Human Judgment
Rate it:
Open Preview
Kindle Notes & Highlights
Read between September 16 - November 21, 2021
32%
Flag icon
People are prepared to trust an algorithm that achieves a very high level of accuracy because it gives them a sense of certainty that matches or exceeds that provided by the internal signal. But giving up the emotional reward of the internal signal is a high price to pay when the alternative is some sort of mechanical process that does not even claim high validity.
32%
Flag icon
Despite all the evidence in favor of mechanical and algorithmic prediction methods, and despite the rational calculus that clearly shows the value of incremental improvements in predictive accuracy, many decision makers will reject decision-making approaches that deprive them of the ability to exercise their intuition. As long as algorithms are not nearly perfect—and, in many domains, objective ignorance dictates that they will never be—human judgment will not be replaced. That is why it must be improved.
32%
Flag icon
the Fragile Families study.
33%
Flag icon
Statistical terms are often misleading to the lay reader, and “significant” may be the worst example of this. When a finding is described as “significant,” we should not conclude that the effect it describes is a strong one. It simply means that the finding is unlikely to be the product of chance alone.
33%
Flag icon
To understand is to describe a causal chain. The ability to make a prediction is a measure of whether such a causal chain has indeed been identified. And correlation, the measure of predictive accuracy, is a measure of how much causation we can explain.
33%
Flag icon
while correlation does not imply causation, causation does imply correlation.
33%
Flag icon
why do professionals—and why do we all—seem to underestimate our objective ignorance of the world?
33%
Flag icon
A different mode of thinking, which comes more naturally to our minds, will be called here causal thinking. Causal thinking creates stories in which specific events, people, and objects affect one another.
33%
Flag icon
the logical end of a chain of events, the inevitable denouement of a foreordained tragedy.
33%
Flag icon
Whatever the outcome (eviction or not), once it has happened, causal thinking makes it feel entirely explainable, indeed predictable.
33%
Flag icon
You would be surprised to find we suddenly switched to Turkish,
34%
Flag icon
Causal thinking avoids unnecessary effort while retaining the vigilance needed to detect abnormal events.
34%
Flag icon
statistical thinking also demands specialized training. This type of thinking begins with ensembles and considers individual cases as instances of broader categories. The eviction of the Joneses is not seen as resulting from a chain of specific events but is viewed as a statistically likely (or unlikely) outcome, given prior observations of cases that share predictive characteristics with the Joneses.
34%
Flag icon
Relying on causal thinking about a single case is a source of predictable errors. Taking the statistical view, which we will also call the outside view, is a way to avoid these errors.
34%
Flag icon
causal mode comes much more naturally to us. Even explanations that should properly be treated as statistical are eas...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
34%
Flag icon
Consider assertions such as “they failed because they lacked experience” or “they succeeded because they had a brilliant leader.” It would be easy for you to think of counterexamples, in which inexperienced teams succeeded and brilliant leaders failed. The correlations of experience and brilliance with success are at best moderate and probably low. Yet a causal attribution is readily made. Where causality is plausible, our mind easily turns a correlation, however low, into a causal and explanator...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
34%
Flag icon
The reliance on flawed explanations is perhaps inevitable, if the alternative is to give up on understanding our world. However, causal thinking and the illusion of understanding the past co...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
34%
Flag icon
Causal thinking helps us make sense of a world that is far less predictable than we think. It also explains why we view the world as far more predictable than it really is.
34%
Flag icon
In the valley of the normal, there are no surprises and no inconsistencies. The future seems as predictable as the past. And noise is neither heard nor seen.
35%
Flag icon
people who are asked a difficult question use simplifying operations, called heuristics.
35%
Flag icon
planning fallacy.
36%
Flag icon
The substitution of one question for the other causes predictable errors, called psychological biases.
36%
Flag icon
Errors are bound to occur when a judgment of similarity is substituted for a judgment of probability,
36%
Flag icon
availability heuristic.
36%
Flag icon
conclusion bias, or prejudgment.
37%
Flag icon
affect heuristic: people determine what they think by consulting their feelings.
37%
Flag icon
regardless of the true reasons for your belief, you will be inclined to accept any argument that appears to support it, even when the reasoning is wrong.
37%
Flag icon
Whether you’re haggling in a bazaar or sitting down for a complex business transaction, you probably have an advantage in going first, because the recipient of the anchor is involuntarily drawn to think of ways your offer could be reasonable.
37%
Flag icon
excessive coherence: we form coherent impressions quickly and are slow to change them.
37%
Flag icon
(Another term to describe this phenomenon is the halo effect, because the candidate was evaluated in the positive “halo” of the first impression.
37%
Flag icon
consumers were found to be more likely to be affected by calorie labels if they were placed to the left of the food item rather than the right. When calories are on the left, consumers receive that information first and evidently think “a lot of calories!” or “not so many calories!” before they see the item. Their initial positive or negative reaction greatly affects their choices. By contrast, when people see the food item first, they apparently think “delicious!” or “not so great!” before they see the calorie label.
37%
Flag icon
In general, we jump to conclusions, then stick to them.
37%
Flag icon
substitution biases, which lead to a misweighting of the evidence; conclusion biases, which lead us either to bypass the evidence or to consider it in a distorted way; and excessive coherence, which magnifies the effect of initial impressions and reduces the impact of contradictory information.
38%
Flag icon
a physically attractive candidate whose good looks create an early positive impression in most recruiters. If
38%
Flag icon
When you answer the question “On a scale of 1 to 10, how good is your mood?” or “Please give one to five stars to your shopping experience this morning,” you are matching:
39%
Flag icon
(The technical term for such prediction errors is that they are nonregressive, because they fail to take into account a statistical phenomenon called regression to the mean.)
39%
Flag icon
substitution and matching do not always govern predictions. In the language of two systems, the intuitive System 1 proposes quick associative solutions to problems as they arise, but these intuitions must be endorsed by the more reflective System 2 before they become beliefs.
39%
Flag icon
people are more reluctant to match predictions to unfavorable than to favorable evidence. We suspect that you would hesitate to make a matching prediction of inferior colle...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
39%
Flag icon
We offer the outside view as a corrective for intuitive predictions of all kinds.
39%
Flag icon
When serious judgment is necessary, the outside view must be part of the solution.
40%
Flag icon
an all-time classic article in psychology, published in 1956: “The Magical Number Seven, Plus or Minus Two.” Beyond this limit, people tend to start to make errors
40%
Flag icon
This limit of our discriminating power matters, because our ability to match values across intensity dimensions cannot be better than our ability to assign values on these dimensions.
40%
Flag icon
There is a way to overcome the limited resolution of adjective scales: instead of using labels, use comparisons. Our ability to compare cases is much better than our ability to place them on a scale.
40%
Flag icon
Explicit comparisons between objects of judgment support much finer discriminations than do ratings of objects evaluated one at a time.
40%
Flag icon
“Both of us say this movie is very good, but you seem to have enjoyed it a lot less than I did. We’re using the same words, but are we using the same scale?”
40%
Flag icon
“It is hard to remain consistent when grading these essays. Should you try ranking them instead?”
41%
Flag icon
Much research has been conducted on the difficulties of communication that arise from vague expressions such as “beyond a reasonable doubt,” “clear and convincing evidence,” “outstanding performance,” and “unlikely to happen.” Judgments that are expressed in such phrases are inevitably noisy because they are interpreted differently by both speakers and listeners.
41%
Flag icon
reprehensible;
41%
Flag icon
To test this outrage hypothesis, we asked different groups of participants to answer either the punitive intent question or the outrage question.
41%
Flag icon
the correlation between the mean ratings of outrage and of punitive intent was a close-to-perfect 0.98 (PC = 94%). This correlation supports the outrage hypothesis: the emotion of outrage is the primary determinant of punitive intent.
1 7 13