More on this book
Community
Kindle Notes & Highlights
Read between
November 3 - November 6, 2020
The long absence of science is therefore not to be explained by some particular train of events or some specific mix of custom and circumstance. It spans democracies and theocracies, east and west, pantheists and People of the Book. It seems, to all the world, that there is something about the nature of science itself that the human race finds hard to take on board. That, I believe, is the answer: science is an alien thought form. To understand its late arrival on the human scene, we need to appreciate the inherent strangeness of the scientific method.
Frank Hermens liked this
Science, by contrast, requires of its practitioners the strategic suppression of human nature, indeed, the suppression of the highest element of human nature, the rational mind.
That is the Kuhnian answer to the motivation problem: mold scientists’ minds so that they fail to see that their research might be based on an error, on a false presupposition. If the validity of the paradigm is accepted without question, then the value of long and arduous empirical toil is also beyond question. The purpose of narrowing scientists’ horizons is to encourage them to work harder, to dig deeper, to go further than they would go if they could see their destination in perspective, if they had an accurate sense of their project’s proportion. Ultimately, it is only because scientists’
...more
Science, in the radical subjectivist view, is just another venue for the Machiavellian masterpiece theater that is the human condition.
Frank Hermens liked this
Science is driven onward by arguments between people who have made up their minds and want to convert or at least to confute their rivals. Opinion that runs hot-blooded ahead of established fact is the life force of scientific inquiry. For these reasons, Popper is now thought by most philosophers of science to fall short of providing a rule for bringing evidence to bear on theories that is both fully objective and adequate to science’s needs. What kind of rule might do better? There is philosophical consensus on this matter, too—and the answer is none. An objective rule for weighing scientific
...more
The auxiliary assumptions are like links in a chain leading from the theory to the evidence. The chain is only as strong as its weakest link; thus, to assess the strength of the chain—to assess the strength of a piece of evidence for or against a hypothesis—you must have an opinion about the strength of each of the links.
A rule that strives to lay down the law about the significance of scientific evidence, then, must also lay down the law about the likelihood of all relevant auxiliary assumptions, in the same way that a procedure for determining chain strength must estimate the strength of every link. The rule’s judgments can be objectively valid only if its estimates of the auxiliary’s likelihoods are objectively valid. An objective rule for weighing any and every piece of evidence is therefore possible only if there is an objective fact of the matter about the likelihood of each relevant auxiliary
...more
So it goes with all scientific reasoning: the interpretation of evidence demands likelihoods, and scientists are not only permitted but encouraged to use their subjective plausibility rankings in that role.
Here, then, in short, is the iron rule: 1. Strive to settle all arguments by empirical testing. 2. To conduct an empirical test to decide between a pair of hypotheses, perform an experiment or measurement, one of whose possible outcomes can be explained by one hypothesis (and accompanying cohort) but not the other. There lies the nub of the scientific method and so, once its subtleties have been spelled out in the chapters to come, the denouement of the Great Method Debate.
Physics after Aristotle bifurcated into two schools, the Epicureans and the Stoics, the one affirming an atomistic view in which the universe is composed of nothing more than particles careening blindly through the emptiness of space, the other a view in which matter fills the universe according to the dictates of rationality. An individual seeking enlightenment while Stoicism and Epicureanism held sway, from about 300 BCE to 300 CE, could choose one school or the other or attempt to learn from both, but the schools themselves remained detached intellectual traditions, separated by both their
...more
As evidence accumulates, plausibility rankings begin to converge. Differences in opinion become less extreme. Consensus emerges as to which are the leading theoretical contenders and which are the also-rans, then eventually on which is the best of them all. There is not complete agreement, but there is ever less disagreement. This is Baconian convergence.
What happened in the case of general relativity, and what tends to happen in science more generally, is that opinions converge not because bad data is corrected but because it is swamped.
So we see that over the decades and centuries, agreement emerges again and again from the tissue of uncertainty and dissent that is the characteristic stuff of science—provided that everyone keeps arguing and the stock of observations continues to grow.
The historian David Lindberg provides a partial list of experimenters at work before the Scientific Revolution that stretches from the ancient Roman Empire to Islamic Persia through the European Middle Ages, including, among many others, Ptolemy, Ibn al-Haytham (Alhazen), Kamāl al-Dīn, Theodoric of Freiberg, Rabbi Levi ben Gershon, Johannes de Muris, and Paul of Taranto.
The Four Innovations That Made Modern Science 1. A notion of explanatory power on which all scientists agree 2. A distinction between public scientific argument and private scientific reasoning 3. A requirement of objectivity in scientific argument (as opposed to reasoning) 4. A requirement that scientific argument appeal only to the outcomes of empirical tests (and not to philosophical coherence, theoretical beauty, and so on)
Late in the seventeenth century, the philosophically unified machinery of inquiry in which the wheels and cogs rotate as one was spiked. Newton was the saboteur, and thus he was the chief architect of modern science’s first great innovation. Rather than deep philosophical understanding, Newton pursued shallow explanatory power, that is, the ability to derive correct descriptions of phenomena from a theory’s causal principles, regardless of their ultimate nature and indeed regardless of their very intelligibility.
Every reader, then, pours their own plausibility rankings onto the desiccated framework of a scientific article, bringing it to life and drawing conclusions accordingly—conclusions that are saturated with subjectivity and that consequently differ from scientist to scientist.
EUROPE, once Luther’s “Ninety-Five Theses” went out, was forever to be spiritually divided—the new Protestant versus the old Catholic faith; citizens, rulers, and territories of opposing religions living uneasily side by side. Violence followed soon enough: popular revolt in Germany in the 1520s; English dissidents burned at the stake in the 1550s; the desecration of churches in the Low Countries in the 1560s; full-scale war in France from then through the end of the century. It was to get worse. In 1618, the Protestant nobles of Bohemia, rightly fearing for their religious freedom, spurned
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
The knowledge machine, in its contemporary realization, is highly effective at advancing human goods, but it is not a high expression of what is humanly good.
The bitter fate of humanist thought has been to see its glorification of the full, unifying intellectual potential of the human mind eclipsed by the immensely greater contribution to our knowledge of the natural world made by the lean scientific spirit—to comprehend the meagerness of what is found beyond the golden gate of the imagination when measured against the riches brought back through the low and shameful gate of experience.
When I suggest that science will better flourish if allowed to go its own way, then, Collins and Pinch might think that I have given a bad answer to the wrong question. What we should ask is: how can science be reined in? The archetypical golem was brought into being in the late 1500s by the leading rabbi of Prague, Judah Loew ben Bezalel, to protect the city’s Jewish population. According to one account, when it began to run amok, the rabbi had to take back the animating incantation—emet, the Hebrew word for truth—from the golem’s mouth. His creation turned to dust. In the legend, you might
...more
That is my project, too. I do not, as you know, endorse the understanding of science proposed by subjectivists such as Collins and Pinch. They have overlooked the iron rule; consequently, they have missed the scientific method. Restore the method to its proper place at the heart of the machine, however, and the image of the golem retains its force. The golem of legend was made of clay and brought to life by a magic word. The science golem’s raw material is people, organized and empowered by the iron rule. (It is bronze, not iron, but otherwise the sculptor Eduardo Paolozzi’s transmogrification
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.