Kindle Notes & Highlights
Read between
August 12 - October 3, 2020
The burgeoning field of behavioral economics has produced a new set of justifications for paternalism. This book challenges behavioral paternalism on multiple levels, from the abstract and conceptual to the pragmatic and applied. Behavioral paternalism relies on a needlessly restrictive definition of rational behavior. It neglects nonstandard preferences, experimentation, and self-discovery. It relies on behavioral research that is often incomplete and unreliable. It demands a level of knowledge from policymakers that they cannot reasonably obtain. It assumes a political process largely immune
...more
Much has been written about whether real people are “rational” and the kinds of errors they may be subject to. Unfortunately, economists, and perhaps other social scientists as well, have been boxed into an excessively narrow and technical concept of rationality. This has left its imprint on the influential heuristics-and-biases literature, which claims people are not fully rational relative to that standard. It worries us that much of the core behavioral literature is often presented as essentially settled, and many alleged biases have now attained the status of truisms. One of our tasks in
...more
Experimental evidence suggests that individuals may systematically deviate from the behavior that would best satisfy their own preferences. The list of alleged deviations from strict rationality includes – but is not limited to – status quo bias, optimism bias, susceptibility to framing effects, poor processing of information, and lack of willpower or self-control. To the extent that these phenomena cause people to make errors, paternalist policies can in principle help them to do better – not by some exogenous standard, but by their own standards. This is the defining feature of new
...more
In this book, we will defend what we call inclusive rationality. Inclusive rationality means purposeful behavior based on subjective preferences and beliefs, in the presence of both environmental and cognitive constraints. This notion of rationality preserves the core notion of purposefulness, and in that sense it should seem familiar. But unlike other notions of rationality – many of which were invented for modeling purposes but have since taken on a life of their own – inclusive rationality does not dictate the normative structure of preferences and beliefs a priori. Instead, it allows a
...more
Modeled rationality is always incomplete and bounded relative to what it could be in another model. Recognizing this fact does not automatically open the door to normative criticism. There will always be some standpoint from which agents are deficient. The key issue is whether that standpoint is important and relevant to the agents themselves.
Rationality does not imply that human beings have their minds fully made up on the first day about the relative desirability of all alternatives in all states of the world at all points in time. To assert this is an artificial construct of modeling. Whatever the usefulness of the construct in explaining or predicting aggregate behavior, we can see no plausible argument for declaring individuals “irrational” who may be simply undecided. They are in a process of self-discovery. They do not need fixing.
How does embracing an ongoing process of preference formation affect the behavioral paternalists’ normative project? To be blunt, it robs them of the Archimedean point that they would use to judge outcomes. If preferences do not exist independently of the act of choice, then there is no preference set against which to judge the individual’s choices as deficient.
What happens when one belief implies a further statement? Must the agent submit to logic and believe the implied statement? Not necessarily and certainly not generally. The individual may find that the implied statement is completely implausible and therefore decide to reject the initial premise. This occurs often and is good reasoning. The rules of logic are constraints on the relation between propositions. They do not tell people what to believe, pure and simple. Thus, logic is not the whole of reason.
We have found that the literature on cognitive biases, vast though it is, tends to fail in one fundamental respect: recognizing the pragmatic and contextual nature of rational decision-making. The mistake that is constantly and consistently made is to equate rationality with an abstract system of thought unrelated to the purposes and plans of individuals in the environments in which they find themselves. In a related manner, the literature also fails to take into account the socially legitimate expectations of the participants in experiments that the researchers should not provide extraneous
...more
Standard economics is particularly ill-equipped to deal with the process of automatic counteractive self-control. Most choice problems are conceived as the agent maximizing an objective function. In the more recent extended versions, designed to accommodate behavioral insights, an extra constraint is added: self-control. This is costly impulse control – the deliberate application of cognitive effort to resist temptations. But the modeled agent’s perception of the problem, and thus the framework of decision, is itself static.58 The agent takes the parameters of the problem, including the costs
...more
Theoretically, i.e., if everything else is held constant, the replacement of a sugary product with an artificially sweetened product that yields no energy should result in the loss of weight. But people do not live in an everything-else-held-constant world. The theoretical potential for weight loss will be realized only if the artificially sweetened beverages are actually used in the right way.5 But “evidence that use of NNS [nonnutritive sweeteners] in free-living individuals results in improved weight loss or maintenance is lacking” (Mattes and Popkin 2009, 9).
The new, lower thresholds increased the number of Americans classified as overweight or obese by more than 35 million overnight (Kuczmarski and Flegal 2000). What motivated the WHO and NIH to adopt the new recommendations? We cannot say for sure, but we can venture an educated guess. The WHO report, which heavily influenced the NIH’s later decision to change the BMI thresholds, “was drafted and written under the auspices of the International Obesity Task Force (IOTF),” an organization “primarily funded by Hoffman-LaRoche (the maker of the weight-loss drug Xenical) and Abbott Laboratories (the
...more
Behavioral economics indicates that certain types of argument will be more likely to succeed in the political sphere: those that emphasize the urgent need for taking action; those that downplay complexity and emphasize simple solutions; those that flatter people’s current beliefs and attitudes; those that rely on easily recalled and vivid illustrations of alleged problems; and those that emphasize the benevolent goals of the policies in question. Given these tendencies, we should expect the highly motivated parties mentioned earlier to exploit them to advance their agendas. Activists,
...more
In the world of puppet rationality, there is little room for people to learn about themselves, to discover their own weaknesses and foibles, or to find ways to shape and correct their own behavior. Why not? Because the work has already been done, instantaneously and costlessly, by assumption. Their preferences are fully formed and comprehensive, evaluating and ranking all objects of choice in the present and future in all possible states of the world. Their beliefs about all matters, significant and trivial, are complete, unambiguous, and fully consistent with one another. Real people, on the
...more
At the conceptual and philosophical level, behavioral paternalists have yet to grapple adequately with the thicket of thorny issues that arise in trying to identify people’s true preferences. They have not yet managed to fill in the gaping chasm between identifying inconsistencies among individual preferences on the one hand and choosing which preferences to favor on the other. They have also not yet grappled with the evidence indicating that fast-and-frugal non-Bayesian heuristics can perform better in real-world environments. They have hardly begun to fill the gaps in knowledge required to
...more
One possible conclusion is that we should reject behavioral economics in its entirety and revert to the neoclassical approach – one that largely rejected paternalistic thinking. But that would be far too simplistic. It would be a mistake to cling tightly to sterile models of human behavior that have no room for inchoate preferences, self-discovery, trial and error, and self-regulation. While the simplified models of neoclassical theory may still be useful for particular purposes and contexts, they cannot provide a panoptic picture of human decision-making. They cannot capture the full depth
...more
What the discipline does need, however, is a strong dose of humility – particularly for those behavioral researchers looking for policy applications of their work. It is jarring, to say the least, to see social scientists pointing out the errors of private individuals – and then failing to consider that social scientists and policymakers are also subject to error. It is frustrating to see behavioral researchers demonstrating the complexity of real decision-making processes – and then ignoring that complexity when recommending regulatory corrections of those very processes. It is simply
...more