The Big Picture: On the Origins of Life, Meaning, and the Universe Itself
Rate it:
Open Preview
10%
Flag icon
The secret here is to accept that such questions may or may not have answers.
11%
Flag icon
It’s not surprising that ancient cosmologists, when theorizing about the universe, took as its fulcrum the thing they understood the best: themselves.
12%
Flag icon
the Big Bang doesn’t actually mark the beginning of our universe; it marks the end of our theoretical understanding.
12%
Flag icon
It’s been popular to imagine that the world is teleological—directed toward some future goal. But it’s better to think of it as ekinological, from the Greek “εκκίνηση,” meaning “start” or “departure.”
13%
Flag icon
Physical motions, to the best of our understanding, are reversible.
13%
Flag icon
Both directions of time are on an equal footing.
13%
Flag icon
Boltzmann.
13%
Flag icon
identify the entropy of a system with the number of different states that would be macroscopically indistinguishable from the state it is actually in. (Technically, it’s the logarithm of the number of indistinguishable states,
13%
Flag icon
In equilibrium, time has no arrow.
13%
Flag icon
very low-entropy state.
13%
Flag icon
Past Hypothesis.
13%
Flag icon
Nobody knows exactly why the early universe had such a low entropy. It’s one of those features of our world that may have a deeper explanation we haven’t yet found, or may just be a true fact we need to learn to accept.
15%
Flag icon
Our progress through time is pushed from behind, not pulled from ahead.
15%
Flag icon
frequentists,
15%
Flag icon
Bayesians,
15%
Flag icon
credences.
16%
Flag icon
prior credences.
16%
Flag icon
If we think our opponent would draw precisely one card only 10 percent of the time if they had a pair, we remove nine-tenths of the grains of sand from the jar labeled “pair”
17%
Flag icon
18%
Flag icon
the absence of consistency across sacred texts counts as evidence against theism.
18%
Flag icon
Bayes’s Theorem is one of those insights that can change the way we go through life.
19%
Flag icon
“Boltzmann Brain”
20%
Flag icon
set our prior credence in radically skeptical scenarios at very low values,
20%
Flag icon
if we take the world roughly at face value, we have a way of moving forward.
20%
Flag icon
there are many ways of talking about the world, each of which captures a different aspect of the underlying whole.
21%
Flag icon
The classic example of emergence, one you should constantly return to whenever these things get confusing, involves the air in the room around you.
21%
Flag icon
The different stories or theories use utterly different vocabularies; they are different ontologies, despite describing the same underlying reality.
21%
Flag icon
Each theory has a particular domain of applicability.
21%
Flag icon
Within their respective domains of applicability, each theory is autonomous—
21%
Flag icon
If we have two different theories that both accurately describe the same underlying reality, they must be related to each other and mutually consistent.
21%
Flag icon
we often call the first theory the “microscopic” or “fine-grained” or “fundamental” one, and the second the “macroscopic” or “coarse-grained” or “emergent” or “effective” one.
21%
Flag icon
trade-off between comprehensiveness of a theory and its practicality.
22%
Flag icon
All we’re really doing to derive the fluid description is calculating the average properties of all the molecules.
22%
Flag icon
Quantum mechanics, in particular, features the phenomenon of entanglement.
22%
Flag icon
space itself is emergent rather than fundamental.
22%
Flag icon
phase transition.
24%
Flag icon
strong emergence, the behavior of a system with many parts is not reducible to the aggregate behavior of all those parts, even in principle.
24%
Flag icon
“strong emergence” (all stories are autonomous, even incompatible) on one end
24%
Flag icon
and “strong reductionism” (all stories reduce to one fundamental one) on the other.
24%
Flag icon
eliminativism,
24%
Flag icon
Atoms are real; tables are real;
24%
Flag icon
“model-dependent realism.”)
25%
Flag icon
How poetic naturalism divides up “fundamental” versus “emergent/effective,” “real” versus “illusion,” and “objective” versus “subjective.”
25%
Flag icon
whole systems of belief fit together with one another, in more or less comfortable ways, pulled in by a mutual epistemological force.
26%
Flag icon
self-serving bias:
26%
Flag icon
Confirmation bias
27%
Flag icon
the number X that we obtain by multiplying together all of the primes from our list, exactly once each, and adding 1 to the result. Then X is clearly larger than any of the primes in our list. But it is not divisible by any of them, since dividing by any of them yields a remainder
28%
Flag icon
it’s a good thing that credences never reach these points of absolute certainty; if they did, no amount of new evidence could ever change our minds.
28%
Flag icon
we want to avoid being sucked into a black hole of belief, where our convictions are so strong that we can never escape, no matter what kind of new insight or information we obtain.
28%
Flag icon
useful to distinguish between “knowing” and “knowing with absolute logical certainty.” If our credence for some proposition is 0.0000000001, we’re not absolutely certain it’s wrong—but it’s okay to proceed as if we know it is.