More on this book
Kindle Notes & Highlights
But it is vital for Damian’s wider aim, which is to ensure that God is capable of offering redemption to humankind, that is, restoring their moral perfection. At stake here is nothing less than the possibility of the narrative of Christianity itself. To Damian, this would be a matter of considerably greater importance than clarifying our ideas
about possibility and necessity. In this respect, his letter is of a piece with his other activities, such as fighting for the purity of the Church and acting as a spokesman for the virtues of eremitic monasticism. Virginity stands for the spiritual purity that he was striving for throughout his career, and its restoration stands for the cleansing of sin through divine grace.10
Still anxious not to curtail God’s power, Damian seeks refuge in the traditional thought that evil is non-being or nothingness, as Eriugena had done in his treatise on predestination (see above, Chapter 3). Thus, even if we say that God is unable to do sin, there is literally nothing—no positive reality—that lies beyond the scope of God’s power.
He would not make Rome both exist and not exist in the past. Rather, He would replace its past existence with its
past non-existence. There’s nothing impossible about that, unless of course we think that the past is necessary and unalterable. Here another interpretation presents itself.12 Damian follows Boethius’ lead in holding that God is eternal in the strongest sense of not being subject to time at all (§17, 618c). This means that, even if Rome’s existence is necessary from our point of view, because it lies in our past, it may not be necessary from God’s point of view. He stands outside of time, surveying all things at once. For Him, then, the past is no more necessary than the future.
We can expand on this interpretation in light of a distinction that Damian makes between two kinds of necessity,
which we might call absolute and subsequent necessity.14 Something is absolutely necessary if it intrinsically cannot be otherwise. For instance, it is absolutely necessary that one plus one is two. By contrast, some things are necessary only on a certain assumption (§7, 603a). For instance, if we assume that you will finish reading this chapter, it necessarily follows from this that you will have read the chapter’s last sentence. But your having read that sentence would not become absolutely necessary: it would remain the case that you could have refrained from reading it.
God’s timeless eternity remains relevant here, in that His relationship to past, present, and future events is always the same (unlike our case, where the future is open and the past and present closed).
Behind that argument lurks a fundamental presupposition. Things in the created world can only be rightly understood in light of their purposes. To some extent, this was old news. Ever since Aristotle, nature had usually been understood in a teleological way.
We might assume that truth is a pretty straightforward notion: a sentence is true if what it says matches the way that things are. Anselm would agree with that, but he would insist that affirmative sentences also need to be understood as serving some purpose. They are, as it were, trying to do something. Their goal is to describe the world, or as Anselm puts it, “to signify that what is, is” (On Truth §1). So the truth of an assertion is an example of what Anselm calls rectitudo, meaning “correctness,” or if you prefer to stick closer to the Latin word, “rectitude.” In light of this, Anselm
...more
Here Anselm is raising the question we just discussed in Chapter 6, as to whether there is anything that God cannot do. His answer is yes: God cannot will evil.7 He can only will one thing, namely the good. But this does not make Him any less free. In fact, God’s inability to choose anything but goodness makes him more free than a creature who can choose between good and evil (§1). This may sound perplexing, but it is easier to understand in light of Anselm’s earlier definition of the will. Remember that the will is not just a power to choose, but has a purpose.8 This purpose is, as Anselm
...more
can persevere in willing goodness or justice because they are good and just, rather than to win some reward or avoid some punishment (§3). Obviously being unable to sin, like God and the good angels, does not inhibit the ability to persevere in goodness. To the contrary, it ensures that the will is always used in the way it was meant to be used. In other words, an incapacity for sin actually guarantees freedom.
In the same way, even in their fallen state humans have the power to preserve rectitude for its own sake. In other
words, they do have free will. It’s just that they can’t use this power in the way it was meant to be used, at least not without God’s help. But that isn’t to say that humans can’t use free will at all. We are willing freely with every choice we make, including our sinful choices. Why, though, does sinning count as a use of free will at all, if the purpose of the will is to preserve rectitude? Well, because you can use a power without using it rightly.
This is what the will to sin has in common with the will to preserve rectitude. Neither is coerced by any outside force. Whether the choice is good or bad, the choice is only free if it is determined by the person who is exercising their will to choose.
But that’s no problem, because no one else is responsible for giving God this single motivation, as He would have been responsible for giving such a motivation to the angels. Since God’s goodness comes entirely from within, there is no hint of coercion in His choice, and He remains fully self-determined and free. With all due respect to Eriugena, I have to say that this is an unprecedentedly sophisticated and clear-minded attempt to make sense of Augustine’s position on freedom. With a deft series of distinctions and definitions, Anselm has secured everything an Augustinian might want. There
...more
The formula at the center of the ontological argument describes God as “that than which nothing greater can be conceived.” From this formula, Anselm wants to infer not just that God exists and indeed necessarily exists, but also that He is good, powerful, just, eternal, and so on.
It observes that there must be some cause for the goodness we find in the things around us (Monologion §1). Although goodness manifests itself in different ways, goodness itself should have the same meaning in each case. Otherwise we would have no unified idea of goodness, only a welter of different ideas that are misleadingly expressed by the same word. We need, therefore, to suppose that there is a cause of goodness, which is the source of this shared nature that we find in all good things.4 As the cause of all goodness, this source will itself be good, indeed the most good and great of all
...more
As Anselm will later point out in his replies to Gaunilo’s criticism, this is a subtle but crucial difference. The ontological argument would not work if we just said that God is greater than anything else (Replies §5). We need to say that God is that than which nothing greater exists or indeed could exist: “that than which nothing greater can be conceived.” This leaves room for Anselm to admit that God outstrips our understanding. If He were the greatest thing we can conceive, then obviously we would be in a position to conceive of Him. But if He is that than which nothing greater can be
...more
Now Anselm sets out to show the Fool that his atheistic position makes no sense. It is contradictory to suppose that God doesn’t exist in reality, but only in the mind, if we understand God as that than which nothing greater can be conceived. This is because, if God existed only in the mind, it would be easy to conceive of things better than Him. Notably, we could conceive of Him as existing in reality and not just in the mind. As Anselm puts the point, “if that than which a greater cannot be thought exists in the mind alone, this same that than which a greater cannot be thought is that than
...more
which a greater cannot be thought to be eternal, because if it were not eternal, we could think of something better: we need just think of something that is eternal. In the same way, it is implied by the formula that the thing in question must exist, because if it didn’t exist, we could conceive of something better than it. The Fool must therefore admit that God exists, on pain of contradicting himself. Like Mr T, Gaunilo pitied the Fool, and argued on his behalf that Anselm’s argument fails. He devised a number of objections, including his famous island analogy (On Behalf of the Fool §6).
...more
How might Anselm respond? We don’t have to guess, because we actually have Anselm’s reply to Gaunilo’s criticisms, a very helpful document for understanding how Anselm thought his proof was supposed to work in the first
place.6 Obviously, to meet the objection he has to show that it makes a difference that we are being asked to think about an island, as opposed to God. The difference is that existence belongs to the very nature of that than which nothing greater can be conceived, whereas existence cannot belong to the very nature of an island. As the American military proved when they were testing atom bombs in the Pacific Ocean, an island is the sort of thing that can go out of existence. So if we find ourselves entertaining the idea of an island that can’t possibly fail to exist, then we are entertaining
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
of something, I am conceiving of it as having a range of properties. Its existence is simply the realization or instantiation in the world of something that has those properties. Whether this same objection can so plausibly be applied to the idea of necessary existence, though, seems to me to be an open question. Even if existence is not a (great-making) property like justice or eternity, the trait of existing necessarily might be. But I think we don’t need to deny that existence, or necessary existence, is a property in order to defeat Anselm’s argument. If the way I’ve set it out does
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
than everything make it clear that it also subsists in itself” (On Be...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
Philosophers call such shared features “universals,” because they belong universally to all the members of a class: thus humanity belongs to all humans. But what exactly is this shared humanity? On the one hand, it seems to play an important role in the world and in our understanding of things. When we know, for instance, that all humans are rational, it seems that we are understanding something not just about you, me, Groucho, or Zeppo, but about humanity itself. What we are understanding is that the possession of humanity implies the possession of rationality. On the other hand, the idea of
...more
The difficulty of accounting for the shared features of things is called the problem of universals. Perhaps the most famous attempt to answer the problem is also the earliest attempt: Plato’s theory of Forms. This theory was apparently intended to explain common characteristics like humanity or largeness by postulating a single, overarching Form or paradigm, humanity-itself or largeness-itself. And readers have traditionally understood Plato’s Forms as universals. This may not be quite right, though. Aristotle points out that although a Platonic Form does play the role of a universal by
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
commentators and their medieval readers, and they had still further reasons of their own to take the problem seriously. Unlike most philosophers nowadays, they followed Aristotle’s lead in believing that knowledge in the strict and proper sense—the kind of knowledge involved in scientific understanding—is universal in scope.3 So, for them, answering Porphyry’s questions was an urgent task in the study of knowledge, or epistemology, as well as in philosophy of language.
We encounter such features in particulars, and then “abstract” or isolate them through a mental process, something Boethius compares to isolating the line that forms the edge of a body
While this goes well beyond the intriguing list of questions posed by Porphyry, Boethius says less than one might want about the humanity that is in Groucho and also in Harpo. Is humanity one and the same thing in both of them? Or is it that we have Groucho’s humanity, which is
one thing, and Harpo’s humanity, which is something else, but these two humanities are similar to one another? If we take the first alternative, we are committed to something that really exists out in the world and is universal. If we take the second alternative, then true universality occurs only in the mind of someone who abstracts and isolates humanity as a general concept. An analogy might help here. The first option would be like your watching the Marx Brothers movie Duck Soup on television while I am watching it in a cinema. One and the same movie is being viewed in two places at the
...more
We find grammatical commentaries close to Roscelin’s approach saying that words have always been introduced to signify some particular substance. Only afterwards do they come to signify other, similar things.6 Someone somewhere would have first used the word “human” and meant by it one particular human. Perhaps it was Adam referring with surprise and delight to Eve, who had just been produced from one of his ribs, and thereafter, as a matter of convention this same word “human” was applied to anything else that seemed to be similar to the first thing that bore the name of human. This does seem
...more
There is a family resemblance between this proposal by William of Champeaux and the “hyper-realism” of the earlier Eriugena and his followers. They believed that every substance is
an expression of a single, archetypal substance, much as all things are ultimately an expression of the transcendent reality that is God. William’s theory was not quite that Platonist, in that it did not assert the existence of some paradigmatic humanity separate from all individual humans. In a way, this was its chief flaw. If humanity in itself is not separate from humans, and if it is one and the same in all humans, then all humans turn out to be numerically identical with each other insofar as they are humans. In other words, Groucho, Chico, and Harpo are all actually one human being.
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
human explains my being rational and alive. So how could it be nothing at all? Abelard responds with an example (§92). Suppose a slave of ancient Rome is beaten because he refuses to go to the forum. His refusing to go is a status, and it explains something, namely why he was beaten. But we are surely not tempted to say that his refusing to go to the forum is actually a thing in its own right. Rather, the man who refuses, and is beaten for it, is a thing. His refusing to go is just a status, one that he lives to regret. This leaves the way clear for Abelard to give his own, positive account of
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
Modern-day scholars have called this approach “vocalism,” alluding to Roscelin’s insistence that dialectic deals with words and not things. With this, Roscelin paved the way for Abelard’s nominalism. Roscelin’s vocalism was not offered as a solution to the problem of universals, but as the key to interpreting the works of logic that were being studied with such intensity at this time. For Roscelin, Porphyry’s Introduction and Aristotle’s Categories were about words, not things. This reading of the texts was anticipated already in antiquity, when it was suggested as a way of defusing potential
...more
Indeed, it would be fair to say that Abelard actually discovered the idea of a proposition, more or less as it is used in philosophy today.
Abelard makes another leap forward when it comes to the question of negating a proposition. For Boethius, the negation of the proposition “A giraffe is in the kitchen cooking dinner” would be “A giraffe is not in the kitchen cooking dinner.” Which looks reasonable enough, and not just because giraffes are notoriously bad cooks. But it has a disadvantage. In stating this denial I seem to be saying something about a certain giraffe, namely that she is not cooking dinner. But what if I wanted to deny the proposition without talking about any giraffe at all? Abelard gives
us the tools to do so, by saying that there are in fact two ways to negate a proposition. In addition to saying “A giraffe is not in the kitchen cooking dinner,” I could say “It is not the case that a giraffe is in the kitchen cooking dinner.” In the latter case, I am not implying that there is a giraffe who might be getting dinner ready if she weren’t so lazy. Abelard calls the first kind of negation “separative,” because it just denies that a predicate is connected to a subject. The second kind is called “destructive,” because what is being denied is the whole proposition rather than the
...more
Actions by themselves, then, are neither good nor bad. So we need to look somewhere else to find right and wrong. An obvious place would be the desires and motivations that bring people to perform their actions.
Plausible though this may seem at first blush, it is problematic to say that motives and desires are the proper objects of moral judgment. After all, can you really be blamed for having wicked desires, the sort of motivations that Abelard calls a “bad will”? Perhaps you are powerfully tempted by opportunities to overeat, betray your friends, and cast aspersions on the Marx Brothers. But we wouldn’t and shouldn’t judge you harshly just for having these desires, so long as you manage to resist them. In fact, Abelard
goes so far as to say that it is more admirable to avoid sin when temptation is powerful. It’s easy to avoid wrongdoing when you have no urge to do wrong, the difficult thing is resisting sins you would very much like to commit. Hence we admire those who struggle against their own bad wills and prevail more than we admire those who have no bad will in the first place (§22). Indeed, you might wonder whether someone who is lucky enough to have a good will is admirable at all. If you are simply the sort of person who gets a kick out of helping old ladies across the street and volunteering for
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
a fight, so that victorious over themselves through the virtue of moderation they might obtain a crown” (§5). Though he doesn’t quite come out and say so, it seems that for him, the most admirable people would be the ones who have the worst desires, while managing to prevail in the struggle against those desires.3 While this aspect of Abelard’s moral theory is, to say the least, open to dispute, he has an almost irresistible argument against the idea that desires and motivat...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
Perhaps, then, we could say something slightly different, namely that the sin consists in enjoying a wrongful action.
So now we seem to be stuck. If morality isn’t a matter of which action you perform, nor a matter of what motivations lead you to act the way you do, nor a matter of taking pleasure in wrongdoing, then where do the wickedness of sin and righteousness of virtue reside? Abelard’s answer is that they lie in consenting to a desire, in other words, in forming an intention to act in a certain way.
In light of this observation, we can now see that there are four stages involved in any action, whether sinful, virtuous, or morally neutral. First, we have a desire or “will” that motivates us to perform the action. We do not necessarily have any control over whether or not we have a certain desire; we may simply find that we have it. What we can control is whether or not we “consent” to a desire, as opposed to resisting it. Giving consent, then, is a second stage, which consists in forming an intention to act on the desire in question. Then, the action itself is a further, third stage. Just
...more
He thinks that sinful intentions are the ones that show “contempt for God” (§113) by consenting to desires that God wants us to
resist. Conversely, good intentions are the ones that would please God (§230), though we don’t hear much about these, because Abelard’s Ethics breaks off just after the start of the second book, which was planned to cover goodness.
Abelard is right to claim common ground with non-Christian thinkers. His ethical theory is similar to that of the Stoics. They also thought that human action involves giving consent to a motivating “impression” that one ought to do something. Abelard is especially close to Roman Stoics like Epictetus, who likewise argued that the morally decisive thing is the exercise of one’s power of choice, or prohairesis.
We are to imagine a poverty-stricken woman who takes her child into her bed to keep him warm, and tragically smothers him in her sleep. Here the desire and the intention to kill the baby are very much absent; yet she might be told by a priest to do penance for what has happened (§79). Why is this? For purely pragmatic reasons, says Abelard. We want to discourage other women from doing the same thing, so we make a lesson of the woman even though she is morally innocent. This is a good answer, I think, and it can be generalized. The reason we spend so much time evaluating, punishing, and
...more