Beyond Weird: Why Everything You Thought You Knew about Quantum Physics Is Different
Rate it:
Open Preview
2%
Flag icon
No, the equations aren’t why quantum mechanics is perceived to be so hard. It’s the ideas. We just can’t get our heads around them. Neither could Richard Feynman. His failure, Feynman admitted, was to understand what the math was saying. It provided numbers: predictions of quantities that could be tested against experiments, and which invariably survived those tests. But Feynman couldn’t figure out what these numbers and equations were really about: what they said about the ‘real world’.
2%
Flag icon
Or maybe, it’s sometimes said, the math tells us that ‘everything that can happen does happen’ – whatever that means.
3%
Flag icon
If anything deserves to be called weird, it is us.
3%
Flag icon
It’s very peculiar that a scientific theory should demand interpretation at all. Usually in science, theory and interpretation go together in a relatively transparent way. Certainly a theory might have implications that are not obvious and need spelling out, but the basic meaning is apparent at once.
4%
Flag icon
Talking about the interpretation of quantum mechanics was, on the other hand, a parlour game suitable only for grandees in the twilight of their career, or idle discussion over a beer. Or worse: only a few decades ago, professing a serious interest in the topic could be tantamount to career suicide for a young physicist. Only a handful of scientists and philosophers, idiosyncratically if not plain crankily, insisted on caring about the answer. Many researchers would shrug or roll their eyes when the ‘meaning’ of quantum mechanics came up; some still do. ‘Ah, nobody understands it anyway!’ How ...more
4%
Flag icon
Such work is already winning Nobel Prizes, and will win more. What it tells us above all else is very clear: the apparent oddness, the paradoxes and puzzles of quantum mechanics, are real. We cannot hope to understand how the world is made up unless we grapple with them.
4%
Flag icon
What has emerged most strongly from this work on the fundamental aspects of quantum theory over the past decade or two is that it is not a theory about particles and waves, discreteness or uncertainty or fuzziness. It is a theory about information. This new perspective gives the theory a far more profound prospect than do pictures of ‘things behaving weirdly’. Quantum mechanics seems to be about what we can reasonably call a view of reality.
4%
Flag icon
So we don’t have all the answers. But we do have better questions, and that’s some kind of progress.
4%
Flag icon
When words come too easily, it’s because we haven’t delved deeply enough
5%
Flag icon
‘If a man does not feel dizzy when he first learns about the quantum of action [that is, quantum theory],’ said Bohr, ‘he has not understood a word.’
5%
Flag icon
Quantum physics implies that the world comes from a quite different place than the conventional notion of particles becoming atoms becoming stars and planets. All that happens, surely: but the fundamental fabric from which it sprang is governed by rules that defy traditional narratives. It is another quantum cliché to imply that those rules undermine our ideas of ‘what is real’ – but this, at least, is a cliché that we might usefully revisit with fresh eyes. The physicist Leonard Susskind is not exaggerating when he says that ‘in accepting quantum mechanics, we are buying into a view of ...more
6%
Flag icon
David Mermin expressed this adeptly when describing how many quantum physicists feel about Niels Bohr himself, who acquired the reputation of a guru with a quasi-mystical understanding that leaves physicists even now poring over his maddeningly cryptic words.
6%
Flag icon
Perhaps quantum mechanics pushes us to the limits of what we can know and comprehend. Well then, let’s see if we can push back a little.
9%
Flag icon
It’s not easy to understand what the words mean, but they reflect the fact that the most fundamental message of quantum theory isn’t a purely mathematical one.
9%
Flag icon
But there was already a mature mathematical theory of classical waves; maybe we could use that to describe the alleged waviness of particles? That’s just what Erwin Schrödinger, a professor of physics at Zurich, did. After being given de Broglie’s thesis and challenged to describe wave-like particles in formal terms, he wrote down an expression for how they might behave. It was not quite like an ordinary wave equation of the sort used to describe water waves or sound waves. But it was mathematically very similar. Why wasn’t it identical? Schrödinger didn’t explain his reason, and it now seems ...more
13%
Flag icon
So quantum particles can tunnel through barriers: well, why not? The feat is not possible within a classical picture, but it’s imaginable if we don’t worry too much about how it was achieved. This doesn’t mean, however, that we should picture the electron wriggling its way through the barrier. We can predict, using the Schrödinger equation, what we will measure in a tunnelling process, but we can’t relate that to an underlying picture of an electron ‘doing’ anything. It’s better to see this effect as a manifestation of the randomness that sits at the core of quantum mechanics. The wavefunction ...more
13%
Flag icon
Does the wavefunction express a limitation on what can be known about reality, or is it the only meaningful definition of reality at all?
13%
Flag icon
This possibility seemed to Einstein to be a profoundly anti-scientific idea, because it meant relinquishing not just a complete description of reality but the notion of causality itself. Things happen, and we can say how likely they are to happen, but we cannot say why they happened just as or when they did. Take radioactive decay. Some radioactive atoms will decay by emitting an electron from inside the nucleus: this electron is, for historical reasons, called a beta particle, but it’s just a common-or-garden electron. Atomic nuclei don’t exactly contain electrons – we saw that these orbit ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
14%
Flag icon
We are suspended in language. From the human perspective, it certainly looks as though quantum objects can possess two different, even contradictory, values of some property at once. But the human perspective is the wrong one for understanding quantum mechanics. Nonetheless, it’s all we have.
20%
Flag icon
The relationship between what we observe and what is has long preoccupied philosophers.
20%
Flag icon
Stephen Hawking has written that ‘mental concepts are the only reality we can know. There is no model-independent test of reality.’
20%
Flag icon
All the same, such ‘paradoxes’ have an important role in illustrating why quantum mechanics confounds intuition. They generally arrange quantum outcomes in such a way as to apparently permit the answers Yes and No simultaneously. Whatever we are to make of that, we must surely aspire to do better than shrug and call it ‘weird’.
21%
Flag icon
This is one of the most challenging, if not infuriating, aspects of quantum theory: it seems to demand that we regularly disregard its insistence on what can and cannot be said.
22%
Flag icon
Nature seems to ‘know’ if we’re making a measurement or not – of the path of a photon or electron through the double slits, say – and changes its behaviour accordingly. It’s as if nature can sense whether or not we are trying to spy on the photon’s path.
22%
Flag icon
Yet in the view of Bohr and Wheeler, there are no fundamental quantum phenomena about which we have any right to speak until we measure them. To the question ‘What was happening to the photon between its emission from the laser and its detection?’, we can’t simply reply ‘I don’t know, I wasn’t looking.’ We have to say ‘Because I wasn’t looking, that question has no meaning.’
23%
Flag icon
Nature always seems to ‘know’ our intentions.
24%
Flag icon
From our perspective the world is made up of phenomena – things happen – and a phenomenon only exists when it has been measured. Wavefunction collapse is simply a name we give to the process by which we turn quantum states into observed phenomena.
24%
Flag icon
Wavefunction collapse is then a generator of knowledge: it is not so much a process that gives us the answers, but is the process by which answers are created.
25%
Flag icon
Should we consider the wavefunction to have collapsed within the measuring device, or within the brain of the human experimenter? At what point in the chain from quantum event to macroscopic measuring device to observer reading the result and noting it in a lab book do we consider collapse to have occurred? Werner Heisenberg pondered this problem, and the point at which we separate the quantum from the classical world became known as the ‘Heisenberg cut’.
25%
Flag icon
Measurement is precisely how we acquire knowledge – so if measurement wasn’t classical, we wouldn’t be able to get any knowledge about a quantum system by experiment.
25%
Flag icon
The problem is that in quantum mechanics it is almost impossible to be unambiguous and consistent, to say what you mean, or perhaps even to know what you mean, because you are dealing with concepts that defy language.
26%
Flag icon
We know that measurements of a quantum system seem to collapse the wavefunction. We most certainly don’t know how, or why, or indeed if that actually happens.
26%
Flag icon
It implies that there is no obvious way to deal with what strikes us as strange about quantum mechanics. Nothing we try will make it go away. It’s for this reason that the proliferation of interpretations is not a failing of quantum mechanics, but a necessity. We need different perspectives, just as we need to look at a sculpture from many different angles to appreciate it fully.
27%
Flag icon
He felt that the ‘active information’ that it could transmit to a particle had parallels with the activity of the mind, turning the entire universe into something resembling a conscious organism. This confers a unity that Bohm called the ‘implicate order’, which underpins the ‘explicate order’ accessible to the senses. Thought exists in the cosmos as a holistic entity akin to the quantum potential, which it would, he said, be ‘wrong and misleading to break . . . up into my thought, your thought’.
28%
Flag icon
Another physical collapse model was devised in the 1980s and 90s by the British mathematical physicist Roger Penrose, and independently by the Hungarian physicist Lajos Diósi. They suggested that collapse might be induced by the disrupting influence of gravity.
28%
Flag icon
It’s not that ‘because the particle went through both slits, there’s an interference pattern’, but rather, ‘the outcome in which there’s an interference pattern contains no meaningful definition of particle trajectories’.
28%
Flag icon
We don’t ban some questions simply because we don’t know what to say about them, but instead recognize that quantum mechanics has no math that can provide an answer: it’s rather like expecting simple arithmetic to tell us what an apple tastes like.
31%
Flag icon
What is impressive is that what Bohr and Einstein (more than any of their contemporaries) had to say remains relevant.
31%
Flag icon
Quantum mechanics might seem ‘weird’, but it is not illogical. It’s just that it employs a new and unfamiliar logic. If you can grasp it – if you can accept that this is just how quantum mechanics works – then the quantum world may stop seeming weird and become just another place, with different customs and traditions and with its own beautiful internal consistency.
36%
Flag icon
Heisenberg’s Uncertainty Principle is not exactly a constraint on how precisely we can make a measurement of some quantum property. Rather, it constrains how precisely the property we want to know about exists at all. It might have been better christened the Unknowability Principle – better still, the Unbeability Principle – although doubtless that would have spawned a mysticism of its own.
38%
Flag icon
But actually Einstein was ‘wrong’ about many things. He made a few trivial lapses in his calculations. He famously fudged his theory of general relativity to avoid its prediction of an expanding universe, just a few years before astronomers found that to be precisely the state of the cosmos. Even his many proofs of the celebrated E = mc2 contained little gaffes. Heck, there’s an entire book enumerating Einstein’s mistakes.*1 None of this has the slightest bearing on Einstein’s status as the greatest scientist of the twentieth century. To imagine that genius implies freedom from error is to ...more
39%
Flag icon
Perhaps too it might seem reassuring to imagine that even Einstein was unable to take an imaginative leap beyond the preconceptions of his early training. The notion that randomness, indeed absence of causality, lies at the heart of things is unsettling in the extreme, and there’s some comfort in seeing that Einstein shared our instinctive reluctance to countenance it.
39%
Flag icon
The emerging appreciation of entanglement’s role in quantum mechanics over the past several decades has shifted the emphasis of the whole field. Entanglement is indeed a real attribute of quantum objects, as numerous careful experiments since the 1970s have demonstrated.
39%
Flag icon
The main thing you need to know about entanglement is this: it tells us that a quantum object may have properties that are not entirely located on that object.
39%
Flag icon
What can it mean to say that an object’s properties are not located solely on that object? My pen is black – the blackness doesn’t have any existence beyond the pen. But what if I were to say that the blackness of my pen is also partly associated with my pencil? I don’t mean that the pencil is black too. I mean that the blackness of the pen is partly in the pencil.
40%
Flag icon
Quantum events don’t appear to have an explanation as such – one in which definable causes lead to specific effects – but only a probability of occurrence. This is what Einstein found unreasonable. Who can pretend that it isn’t?
44%
Flag icon
We can’t regard particle A and particle B in the EPR experiment as separate entities, even though they are separated in space. As far as quantum mechanics is concerned, entanglement makes them both parts of a single object.
44%
Flag icon
What in fact we’re dealing with here is another kind of quantum superposition. We’ve seen that superposition refers to a situation in which a measurement on a quantum object could produce two or more possible outcomes, but we don’t know which it will be, only their relative probabilities. Entanglement is that same idea applied to two or more particles: a superposition of the state in which particle A has spin up and B spin down, say, and the state with the opposite configuration. Although the particles are separated, they must be described by a single wavefunction. We can’t untangle that ...more
45%
Flag icon
It has been proposed, albeit in a highly speculative theoretical scenario, that the interdependence across space that manifests as quantum entanglement is what stitches together the very fabric of space and time, creating the web that allows us to speak of one part of spacetime in relation to another. Spacetime is the four-dimensional fabric described by Einstein’s theory of general relativity, in which it is revealed to have a particular shape. It’s this shape that defines the force of gravity: mass makes spacetime curve, and the resulting motions of objects in that curved arena make manifest ...more
46%
Flag icon
But many researchers suspect that this deep connection between entanglement and spacetime is telling us something about how quantum mechanics and general relativity are related: about what needs to change in our view of spacetime if quantum theory is to be made consistent with general relativity.
« Prev 1