The Emperor's New Mind: Concerning Computers, Minds, and the Laws of Physics (Oxford Landmark Science)
Rate it:
Open Preview
Kindle Notes & Highlights
42%
Flag icon
Consider the two events R and Q in Fig. 5.21. According to S, the event R takes place before the event Q, because R lies on an earlier simultaneous space than Q; but according to M, it is the other way around, Q lying on an earlier simultaneous space than R. Thus, to one observer, the event R takes place before Q, but for the other, it is Q that takes place before R! (This can only happen because R and Q are what are called spatially separated, which means that each lies outside the other’s light cone, so that no material particle or photon can travel from one event to the other.) Even with ...more
Reddle
Re read whole section. Time is contingent on light cones, meaning time is not universal and materials inside the light cone of two events would experience time differently. If two objects are movijng towards me I will see the object closest to me 1st, followed by the second object. However, if there was an observer behind said objects facing me he would see the second object (relative to me) first and the first object (relative to me) second. think of two baseballs being thrown at me to visualise this concept.
43%
Flag icon
The above considerations are ‘local’. However, if one is allowed to make (not quite local) measurements of sufficient precision, one may, in principle, ascertain a difference between a ‘true’ gravitational field and a pure acceleration. In Fig. 5.25 I have shown, a little exaggerated, how an initially stationary spherical arrangement of particles, falling freely under the earth’s gravity, would begin to be affected by the non-uniformity of the (Newtonian) gravitational field. The field is non-uniform on two accounts. First, because the centre of the earth lies some finite distance away, ...more
Reddle
Basically how black holes operate
43%
Flag icon
The geodesics are the curves on that surface which (locally) are ‘shortest routes’.
45%
Flag icon
What is ‘matter’? It is the real substance of which actual physical objects – the ‘things’ of this world – are composed. It is what you, I and our houses are made of. How does one quantify this substance? Our elementary physics text-books provide us with Newton’s clear answer. It is the mass of an object, or of a system of objects, which measures the quantity of matter that it contains. This indeed seems right – there is no other physical quantity that can seriously compete with mass as the true measure of total substance. Moreover it is conserved: the mass, and therefore the total matter ...more
Reddle
Mass is the best source of energy to measure since its conservational.
46%
Flag icon
The conserved quantity that takes over the role of mass is an entire object called the energy–momentum four-vector.
46%
Flag icon
This seems to be pure paradox. Yet, it is a definite implication of what our best classical theories – and they are indeed superb theories – are telling us about the nature of the ‘real’ material of our world. Material reality according to classical theory, let alone in the quantum theory that we are about to explore, is a much more nebulous thing than one had thought. Its quantification – and even whether it is there or not – depends upon distinctly subtle issues and cannot be ascertained merely locally! If such non-locality seems puzzling, be prepared for much greater shocks to come.
47%
Flag icon
To many, the term ‘quantum theory’ evokes merely some vague concept of an ‘uncertainty principle’, which, at the level of particles, atoms or molecules, forbids precision in our descriptions and yields merely probabilistic behaviour. Actually, quantum descriptions are very precise, as we shall see, although radically different from the familiar classical ones. Moreover, we shall find, despite a common view to the contrary, that probabilities do not arise at the minute quantum level of particles, atoms, or molecules–those evolve deterministically – but, seemingly, via some mysterious ...more
47%
Flag icon
Unfortunately, different theorists tend to have very different (though observationally equivalent) viewpoints about the actuality of this picture. Many physicists, taking their lead from the central figure of Niels Bohr, would say that there is no objective picture at all. Nothing is actually ‘out there’, at the quantum level. Somehow, reality emerges only in relation to the results of ‘measurements’. Quantum theory, according to this view, provides merely a calculational procedure, and does not attempt to describe the world as it actually ‘is’. This attitude to the theory seems to me to be ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
48%
Flag icon
How are these puzzles to be resolved? The original Newtonian scheme of particles certainly needs to be supplemented by Maxwell’s field. Can one go to the other extreme and assume that everything is a field, particles being little finite-sized ‘knots’ of some kind of field? This has its difficulties also, for then particles could vary their shapes continuously, wriggling and oscillating in infinitely many different kinds of ways. But this is not what is seen. In the physical world, all particles of the same species appear to be identical. Any two electrons, for example, are just the same as ...more
48%
Flag icon
THE TWO-SLIT EXPERIMENT
49%
Flag icon
There is nothing puzzling about an ordinary macroscopic classical wave travelling through two slits at once in this way. A wave, after all, is just a ‘disturbance’, either of some continuous medium (field), or of some substance composed of myriads of tiny point-like particles. A disturbance could pass partly through one slit and partly through the other. But here things are very different: each individual photon behaves like a wave entirely on its own! In some sense, each particle travels through both slits at once and it interferes with itself!
Reddle
Interesting to note the difference between particle and wave like duality. Waves perturb existing matter, and particles are the substantive mass.
49%
Flag icon
Does the photon actually split in two and travel partly through one slit and partly through the other? Most physicists would object to this way of phrasing things. They would insist that while the two routes open to the particle must both contribute to the final effect, these are just alternative routes, and the particle should not be thought of as splitting into two in order to get through the slits. As support for the view that the particle does not partly go through one slit and partly through the other, the modified situation may be considered in which a particle detector is placed at one ...more
50%
Flag icon
Here, θ is the angle which the pair of points z and w subtend at the origin in the Argand plane (see Fig. 6.9). (Recall that the cosine of an angle is the ratio ‘adjacent/hypotenuse’ for a right-angled triangle. The keen reader who is unfamiliar with the above formula may care to derive it directly, using the geometry introduced in Chapter 3. In fact, this formula is none other than the familiar ‘cosine rule’, slightly disguised!) It is this correction term 2|w||z| |cos θ that provides the quantum interference between quantum-mechanical alternatives. The value of cos θ can range between –1 and ...more
Reddle
This is fucking nuts. Pythagoras how are you so prominent
50%
Flag icon
it is zero (destructive interference!), again in agreement with observation. At the exactly intermediate points we have w = iz or w = – iz (so that cos θ = 0) whence |w + z |2 = |w ± iw |2 = |w|2 + |w |2 = 2|w|2 giving twice the intensity as for just one slit (which would be the case for classical particles). We shall see at the end of the next section how to calculate where the bright, dark, and intermediate places actually are.
50%
Flag icon
quantum level the individual alternative routes have only amplitudes, not probabilities.
51%
Flag icon
I am taking the view that the physical reality of the particle’s location is, indeed, its quantum state ψ.
51%
Flag icon
planes. This will prove useful in our understanding the two-slit experiment. Fig. 6.10. (a) The graph of a real function of a real variable x. (b) The graph of a complex function ψ of a real variable
51%
Flag icon
Here, quantum mechanics provides us with a remarkable economy. The wavefunction ψ already contains the various amplitudes for the different possible momenta!
51%
Flag icon
The interpretation of ψ is that, for each particular choice of p, the complex number ψ(p) gives the amplitude for the particle to have momentum p.
52%
Flag icon
time-development of a wave packet is Schrödinger’s equation, which tells us how the wave-function actually evolves in time. In effect, what Schrödinger’s equation says is that if we decompose
52%
Flag icon
Regarding ψ as describing the ‘reality’ of the world, we have none of this indeterminism that is supposed to be a feature inherent in quantum theory – so long as ψ is governed by the deterministic Schrödinger evolution. Let us call this the evolution process U. However, whenever we ‘make a measurement’, magnifying quantum effects to the classical level, we change the rules. Now we do not use U, but instead adopt the completely different procedure, which I refer to as R, of forming the squared moduli of quantum amplitudes to obtain classical probabilities!4 It is the procedure R, and only R, ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
Reddle
Reason for uncertainties qm
53%
Flag icon
Is there any reason to take such a picture seriously? Can we not regard the photon as simply having a 50 per cent probability that it is in one of the places and a 50 per cent probability that it is in the other? No, we cannot! No matter for how long it has travelled, there is always the possibility that the two parts of the photon’s beam may be reflected back so that they encounter one another, to achieve interference effects that could not result from a probability weighting for the two alternatives.
53%
Flag icon
Of course, such an experiment has never been carried out for path-lengths of the order of a light-year, but the stated result is not seriously doubted (by conventional quantum physicists!). Experiments of this very type have actually been carried out with path-lengths of many metres or so, and the results are indeed in complete agreement with the quantum-mechanical predictions (cf. Wheeler 1983). What does this tell us about the reality of the photon’s state of existence between its first and last encounter with a half-reflecting mirror? It seems inescapable that the photon must, in some ...more
54%
Flag icon
(The ‘Pythagorean theorem’, |ψ|2 = |ψY|2 + |ψN|2, asserts that these probabilities sum to unity, as they should!) Note that the probability that |ψ〉 jumps to |ψY〉 is given by the ratio by which its squared length is reduced upon this projection.
54%
Flag icon
The term ‘spin’ indeed suggests something like the spin of a cricket ball or baseball. Recall the concept of angular momentum which, like energy and momentum, is conserved
Reddle
Spin is conserved by an object which makes it similr to mass which is certainly conservational. This is unlike the classical notion of spin which degrades over time.
55%
Flag icon
A particle whose spin is an odd-number multiple of ℏ/2 (i.e. ℏ/2, 3ℏ/2, or 5ℏ/2 etc.) is called a fermion, and it exhibits a curious quirk of quantum-mechanical description: a complete rotation through 360° sends its state-vector not to itself but to minus itself! Many of the particles of Nature are indeed fermions, and we shall be hearing more about them and their odd ways – so vital to our very existence – later.
Reddle
What fermions are.
55%
Flag icon
The remaining particles, for which the spin is an even multiple of ℏ/2, i.e. a whole-number multiple of ℏ (namely 0, ℏ, 2ℏ, 3ℏ,. . .), are called bosons. Under a 360° rotation, a boson state-vector goes back to itself, not to its negative.
Reddle
What bosons are
55%
Flag icon
This correspondence is called stereo-graphic projection, and it has many beautiful geometrical properties (e.g. it preserves angles and maps circles to circles). The projection gives us a labelling of the points of the sphere by complex numbers together with ∞, i.e. by the set of possible complex ratios q. A sphere labelled in this particular way is called a Riemann sphere. The significance of the Riemann sphere, for the spin states of an electron, is that the direction of spin given by | ↗〉 = w |↑〉 + z |↓〉 is provided by the actual direction from the centre to the point q = z/w as marked on ...more
56%
Flag icon
However, it is possible to copy a quantum state if we are prepared to destroy the state of the original. For example, we could have an electron in an unknown spin-state |α〉 and a neutron, say, in another spin-state |γ〉. It is quite legitimate to exchange these, so that the neutron’s spin-state is now |α〉 and the electron’s is |γ〉. What we cannot do is duplicate |α〉, (unless we already know what |α〉 actually is)! (Cf. also Wootters and Zurek 1982.) Recall the ‘teleportation machine’ discussed in Chapter 1 (p. 35). This depended upon it being possible, in principle, to assemble a complete copy ...more
Reddle
You can't copy quantum states without destroying the original so the idea of teleporting consciousness means your original body is destroyed; sorry bucko.
56%
Flag icon
Photon spin is called polarization, which is the phenomenon on which the behaviour of ‘polaroid’ sunglasses depends.
Reddle
Interesting fact
57%
Flag icon
There is something rather remarkable and puzzling about this description. One is frequently led to believe that, in some appropriate limiting sense, the quantum descriptions of atoms (or elementary particles or molecules) will necessarily go over to classical Newtonian ones when the system gets large and complicated. However, just as it stands, this is simply not true.
57%
Flag icon
In fact, the rules are such that, in a clear sense, particles of a specific type have to be precisely identical not just, say, extremely closely identical. This applies to all electrons, and it applies to all photons. But, as it turns out, all electrons are identical with one another in a different way from the way in which all photons are identical! The difference lies in the fact that electrons are fermions whereas photons are bosons. These two general kinds of particles have to be treated rather differently from one another.
57%
Flag icon
One implication of this is that no two fermions can be in the same state. For if they were, interchanging them would not affect the total state at all, so we would have to have: –|ψ〉 = |ψ〉, i.e. |ψ〉 = 0, which is not allowed for a quantum state. This property is known as Pauli’s exclusion principle,13 and its implications for the structure of matter are fundamental. All the principal constituents of matter are indeed fermions: electrons, protons and neutrons. Without the exclusion principle, matter would collapse in on itself!
60%
Flag icon
Fig. 6.33. Schrödinger’s cat – with additions.
Reddle
Reminds me of an egyptian hieroglyphic wall carving.
61%
Flag icon
VARIOUS ATTITUDES IN EXISTING QUANTUM THEORY
Reddle
Spoot theories qm
61%
Flag icon
Another viewpoint, also logical in its way, but providing a picture no less strange, is that of many worlds, first publicly put forward by Hugh Everett III (1957). According to the many-worlds interpretation, R never takes place at all. The entire evolution of the state-vector – which is regarded realistically – is always governed by the deterministic procedure U. This implies that poor Schrödinger’s cat, together with the protected observer inside the container, must indeed exist in some complex linear combination, with the cat in some superposition of life and death. However the dead state ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
Reddle
Many worlds theory rebutt
61%
Flag icon
At the quantum level, we must treat such ‘alternatives’ as things that can coexist, in a kind of complex-number-weighted superposition. The complex numbers that are used as weightings are called probability amplitudes. Each different totality of complex-weighted alternatives defines a different quantum state, and any quantum system must be described by such a quantum state.
62%
Flag icon
These two evolution procedures were described in a classic work by the remarkable Hungarian/American mathematician John von Neumann (1955). His ‘process 1’ is what I have termed R – ‘reduction of the state-vector’ – and his process 2 is U – ‘unitary evolution’ (which means, in effect that probability amplitudes are preserved by the evolution). In fact, there are other – though equivalent – descriptions of quantum-state evolution U, where one might not use the term ‘Schrödinger’s equation’. In the ‘Heisenberg picture’, for example, the state is described so that it appears not to evolve at all, ...more
Reddle
U and R
63%
Flag icon
Recall the discussion on pp. 260-1 and Fig. 5.22. Two people pass each other on the street; and according to one of the two people, an Andromedean space fleet has already set off on its journey, while to the other, the decision as to whether or not the journey will actually take place has not yet been made. How can there still be some uncertainty as to the outcome of that decision? If to either person the decision has already been made, then surely there cannot be any uncertainty. The launching of the space fleet is an inevitability. In fact neither of the people can yet know of the launching ...more
64%
Flag icon
Highly coordinated motion is acceptable and familiar if it is regarded as being an effect of a large-scale change and not the cause of it. However, the words ‘cause’ and ‘effect’ somewhat beg the question of time-asymmetry. In our normal parlance we are used to applying these terms in the sense that the cause must precede the effect. But if we are trying to understand the physical difference between past and future, we have to be very careful not to inject our everyday feelings about past and future into the discussion unwittingly.
Reddle
Time asymmetry.
64%
Flag icon
However, there is something else involved in our use of the terms ‘cause’ and ‘effect’ which is not really a matter of which of the events referred to happen to lie in the past and which in the future. Let us imagine a hypothetical universe in which the same time-symmetric classical equations apply as those of our own universe, but for which behaviour of the familiar kind (e.g. shattering and spilling of water glasses) coexists with occurrences like the time-reverses of these. Suppose that, along with our more familiar experiences, sometimes water glasses do assemble themselves out of broken ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
64%
Flag icon
Why is it that, in the world in which we happen to live, it is the causes which actually do precede the effects; or to put things in another way, why do precisely coordinated particle motions occur only after some large-scale change in the physical state and not before it? In order to get a better physical description of such things, I shall need to introduce the concept of entropy. In rough terms, the entropy of a system is a measure of its manifest disorder.
66%
Flag icon
Clearly this casts doubt on the original argument. We have not deduced the second law. What that argument actually showed was that for a given low-entropy state (say for a gas tucked in a corner of a box), then, in the absence of any other factors constraining the system, the entropy would be expected to increase in both directions in time away from the given state (see Fig. 7.6). The argument has not worked in the past direction in time precisely because there were such factors. There was indeed something constraining the system in the past. Something forced the entropy to be low in the past. ...more
Reddle
We are the product of a lack of entropy.
66%
Flag icon
We must all be supremely grateful to the green plants – either directly or indirectly – for their cleverness: taking atmospheric carbon dioxide, separating the oxygen from the carbon, and using that carbon to build up their own substance. This procedure, photosynthesis, effects a large reduction in the entropy. We ourselves make use of this low-entropy separation by, in effect, simply recombining the oxygen and carbon within our own bodies. How is it that the green plants are able to achieve this entropy-reducing magic? They do it by making use of sunlight. The light from the sun brings energy ...more
66%
Flag icon
Fig. 7.7. How we make use of the fact that the sun is a hot-spot within the darkness of space.
Reddle
Receiving low entropic energy from the sun
67%
Flag icon
What about the low-entropy nuclear energy in the uranium-235 isotope that is used in nuclear power stations? This did not come originally from the sun (though it may well have passed through the sun at some stage) but from some other star, which exploded many thousands of millions of years ago in a supernova explosion! Actually, the material was collected from many such exploding stars. The material from these stars was spewed into space by the explosion, and some of it eventually collected together (through the agency of the sun) to provide the heavy elements in the earth, including all its ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
Reddle
Where does uranium 235 come from
67%
Flag icon
Now, it follows from the equations of Einstein’s general relativity that this positively closed universe cannot continue to expand forever. After it reaches a stage of maximum expansion, it collapses back in on itself, finally to reach zero size again in a kind of big bang in reverse (Fig. 7.11(b)). This time-reversed big bang is sometimes referred to as the big crunch. The negatively curved and zero-curved (infinite) universe FRW-models do not recollapse in this way. Instead of reaching a big crunch, they continue to expand forever.
Reddle
Einsteins thought on energy rules in the universe
67%
Flag icon
68%
Flag icon
From that moment, one ten-thousandth of a second after creation, until about three minutes later, the behaviour has been worked out in great detail (cf. Weinberg 1977) – and, remarkably, our well-established physical theories, derived from experimental knowledge of a universe now in a very different state, are quite adequate for this.
Reddle
The universes first few minutes of expansion.
68%
Flag icon
Any red giant star will have a white dwarf at its core, and this core will be continually gathering material from the main body of the star. Eventually, the red giant will be completely consumed by this parasitic core, and an actual white dwarf – about the size of the earth – is all that remains. Our sun will be expected to exist as a red giant for ‘only’ a few thousand million years. Afterwards, in its last ‘visible’ incarnation – as a slowly cooling dying ember* of a white dwarf – the sun will persist for a few more thousands of millions of years, finally obtaining total obscurity as an ...more
Reddle
A literal or metaphorical black star- of course the metaphor is analogous to 'nothing'