More on this book
Community
Kindle Notes & Highlights
If I am not for myself, who will be for me? And if I am for myself only, what am I? And if not now, when? RABBI HILLEL
“That which is hateful unto you, do not do unto your neighbor. That is the whole Torah; all the rest is commentary.
Each of us goes through it in his own way, experiences it with greater or lesser intensity, and emerges from it more or less reconciled to the years ahead. It is a “natural” developmental crisis, and it is unavoidable.18
On this new interpretation, the midlife crisis is a predictable dip in life-satisfaction as one reaches middle age, not the tumultuous angst of the original myth. This is how we will picture the midlife crisis in the chapters to come. It is a phase of relative unhappiness that correlates with middle age. At the same time, the U-curve is not irrelevant to more extreme conditions. If average life-satisfaction is lowest at forty-six and there is a variation around the norm—a certain proportion of people being above average, a certain proportion below—we would expect emotional trauma to peak at
...more
People were asked about their current level of overall life-satisfaction and about the level they expected to enjoy in five years’ time. Schwandt learned that younger people tend to over-estimate how satisfied they will be, while mid-lifers underestimate old age.
Immanuel Kant, perhaps the greatest philosopher of the Enlightenment, insists that the “whole interest of . . . reason, whether speculative or practical,” is encapsulated in three questions: “What can I know?”, “What should I do?”, and “What may I hope?”34 Here the universality of the questions comes out, paradoxically, in their first-person character, as questions for anyone.
philosophy has authority, it is the authority of honest persuasion. As in psychotherapy, you should accept only what you can confirm yourself. The difference is that the therapist is a philosopher and the patient is a hypothetical victim of midlife.
“it is the greatest happiness of the greatest number that is the measure of right and wrong.”1 Forget the past, ignore tradition: the institutions of society must answer to the interests of everyone they affect. What does not make us happier must change.
The mystery is why. Why should the achievement of one’s deepest desires, one’s most profound ambitions, be a matter of indifference? What has gone wrong?
Mill reports two marked reversals in his thinking as his sentiments revived. The first is this: I never, indeed, wavered in the conviction that happiness is the test of all rules of conduct, and the end of life. But I now thought that this end was only to be attained by not making it the direct end. Those only are happy (I thought) who have their minds fixed on some object other than their own happiness; on the happiness of others, on the improvement of mankind, even on some art or pursuit, followed not as a means, but as itself an ideal end. Aiming thus at something else, they find happiness
...more
Mill’s insight in this passage has a name: the paradox of egoism.
Butler held that a crucial condition of happiness is caring about things other than oneself. This doesn’t mean you have to be altruistic. What you care about might be baseball, or philosophy, or particular people, your friends and family, not humanity at large. When you care about something in this way, it is not just a means that you exploit for your own sake. Its flourishing makes you happy. And so the sources of happiness, though also of vulnerability, grow. That is Mill’s idea. I think it is a pretty good one. Call it the first rule for preventing a midlife crisis: you have to care about
...more
It is only if human life matters in itself, apart from its effects, that there is any point in altruism. There is value in acting on behalf of others only if there is value in other activities, too. Hence the paradox: if altruism is the only thing that matters, nothing matters. Life is not worth living.
What Mill calls the “other important change” in his opinions was that “for the first time, [he] gave its proper place, among the prime necessities of human well-being, to the internal culture of the individual.”17 By this he meant the expression and refinement of human feelings in the appreciation of art.
Yet if you lose touch with existential value, if you find no place in your life for the activities of the gods—ones that make life worth living to begin with—you risk a midlife crisis not unlike John Stuart Mill’s. If you have the opportunity, you should make yourself immortal, some of the time.
So tell yourself this: although I may regret regret, desire that no desire go unfulfilled, I cannot in the end prefer to have desires that could be fully met. The sense of loss is real; but it is something to concede, not wish away. Embrace your losses as fair payment for the surplus of being alive.
Imagine there are three outcomes, A, B, and C, that you rank in that order. If you were to be assigned an outcome, you would prefer A to B and B to C. Now suppose that having options is important, as Paul believes: the existence of alternatives has final value, in addition to the value of the alternatives themselves. It follows that having B and C as options is better than just getting B, with no alternative. That sounds fine. What is odd is that, if A is only slightly better than B, and there is value in having options, it could make sense to prefer a choice between B and C to just getting A,
...more
What man wants is simply independent choice, whatever that independence may cost and wherever it may lead. And choice, of course, the devil only knows what choice.”
Part of what is awful about Sophie’s dilemma is that, whichever child she picks, she could have saved, even though one of them was bound to die. In this case, it is worse to be made to choose than to have no alternative.
It does makes sense to wish for options, to resent the confinement of one’s position, even when things go well. There is no way now to be a poet or a doctor of the sort I once conceived. If I choose to go on with philosophy, it is not with those alternatives but with others more constrained. In that respect, the meaning of my choice is different from the meaning of my choice at seventeen. Something has been lost. Midlife is missing out not just on other lives but on the meaning for one’s present life of having them as options. Like the colleague quoted at the start, I want to do my job because
...more
At the same time, there is a risk of being fooled, of mistaking a deficit that turns on the loss of possibilities for a defect in the outcome one is living. It is not wrong to lament the limitations of midlife, but it is a confusion to think that they justify radical change, trading in A for a choice between B and C, which makes things worse. The fact is that, absent the ingenuity of Reggie Perrin, your decisions in middle age cannot mean what they did twenty years ago; and even Reggie can’t reverse the passage of time. So, more advice from philosophy, if not another rule. Tell yourself this:
...more
CONSOL...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
We have one last thread to unravel, which brings together past and present, nostalgic yearning and frustrated wish. Our story began with the inevitable fact of missing out, by middle age, on meaningful desires. “You can’t have everything,” quips stand-up Steven Wright, “Where would you put it?”21 Nor is the fact of missing out news. It was true of me at seventeen that I would have to decide which to pursue—poetry, medicine, or philosophy—and I knew it. Despite my dad’s insistence, I would not be happy to read philosophy, or write poems, on the side. But though I was aware that something had to
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
Writer Meghan Daum evokes this ambivalence in a recent essay: Now that I am almost never the youngest person in any room I realize that what I miss most about those times is the very thing that drove me so mad back when I was living in them. What I miss is the feeling that nothing has started yet, that the future towers over the past, that the present is merely a planning phase for the gleaming architecture that will make up the skyline of the rest of my life. But what I forget is the loneliness of all that. If everything is ahead then nothing is behind. You have no ballast. You have no
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
Afflicted with nostalgia, even as things go well, it is wise to recall the desolation of the playground: the uncertainty, confusion, hope, and fear. I submit that nostalgia for lost alternatives is distorted by hindsight. Looking back from a place of relative stability, I project into my youth a degree of assurance that comes from having a more or less secure identity. At the same time, I assume an open future, an ignorance of what is to come that shields me from unsatisfied desire. But the prospect is an illusion. You can’t have it both ways, knowing who you are but not who you are not. The
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
If part of what protects you from regret, or mutes its force, is an asymmetry of knowledge—your comparative ignorance of the lives you could have lived—your tranquility depends on its persistence. In order to avoid regret, you must preserve a measure of oblivion. There is a corresponding threat. The more you know what you are missing, the more you learn what the alternatives would have been and what they would involve, the harder it becomes to let them go. Hence a parting word to the retrospective: be careful what you study, where you choose to train your eye. A little knowledge is harmless;
...more
It is fair to say, I think, that the rationality of future bias is an unsolved problem in philosophy. On the one hand, it is hard to believe that the common response to My Past or Future Operations is irrational. On the other hand, it leads fairly rapidly to peculiar results. Imagine being asked, a week before the operation is scheduled, whether you prefer to have four hours of painful surgery on Monday morning or one hour on Tuesday afternoon. It’s up to you. Unless you are quite unusual, you will opt for Tuesday. If you are future-biased, however, we can predict with confidence that, as you
...more
If we could persuade ourselves that immortality is undesirable, we might be reconciled to death.
There is a crack of light between two darknesses: avoidance of love and inescapable woe. That is where we should steer our ship.
You are not what you plan to get done. And the activities you love need not be projects. Atelic activities, ones that do not aim at terminal states, have value, too. There is pleasure in going for a walk, just wandering or hiking, not to get anywhere, but for the sake of walking itself. Walking is atelic: unlike walking home, it does not aim at its own completion, a point at which there is no more to do.
At the same time, when I try to wrap my mind around the no-self view, I can see why Buddhists believe that it is life-transforming. If I do not exist in anything like the way that I supposed, the meaning of death is utterly changed. I will not cease to exist, after all. Instead, I have to face the fact that I was never there. To accept that fact is to let go of myself, to grieve in advance, relinquishing attachment. A similar change might undermine self-obsession—how can it survive the absence of a self?—and thus transform the character of desire.
At the risk of embarrassment, let me admit how close we are coming to the wisdom of Eckhart Tolle, Oprah Winfrey’s spiritual guru, in his 1997 blockbuster, The Power of Now: If there is no joy, ease, or lightness in what you are doing, it does not necessarily mean that you need to change what you are doing. It may be sufficient to change the how. “How” is always more important than “what.” See if you can give much more attention to the doing than to the result that you want to achieve through it. Give your fullest attention to whatever the moment presents. This implies that you also completely
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
In the hollow of the U-curve, life can seem oppressive, arduous, bleak. Chapter 2 proposed two rules of midlife crisis prevention. First, as we learned from the paradox of egoism: you mustn’t be too self-involved. The obsessive pursuit of happiness interferes with its own achievement: “Those only are happy,” Mill wrote, “who have their minds fixed on some object other than their own happiness; on the happiness of others, on the improvement of mankind, even on some art or pursuit, followed not as a means, but as itself an ideal end. Aiming thus at something else, they find happiness by the
...more
Some words of advice, set out in chapter 3. First, while the feeling of loss around midlife is real, ask yourself what the alternative would be. Missing out is a consequence of the plurality of values: only a drastic impoverishment in the world, or your response to it, could shield you from dismay. Second, do not over-estimate the value of having options. Options matter, but not enough to compensate for outcomes you would not prefer, considered alone. Don’t be fooled by the allure of choice, like Paul O’Rourke and the Underground Man. Third, while it makes sense to envy your younger self, free
...more
This advice falls flat when you regret what you have done or what has happened to you, when you wish you had a second chance. But as we learned in chapter 4, there are ways to reconcile yourself, without illusion, to the failings of the past. First, there is new life. Where those you love would not exist except for your mistakes, you have reason to be glad that those mistakes were made. Second, there is risk aversion. When you imagine starting over, keep in mind the many ways things could have gone, the vast uncertainty, weighed against the history you know. Is it worth the counterfactual
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
Chapter 5 took on the finitude of human life with philosophical tools. First, there is the attitude of temporal neutrality: giving equal weight to past and future gains. If you adopt this view, the deprivations of being dead are no worse than those of being as yet unconceived. Second, to want the benefits of immortality is to want what lies beyond the human condition. It is like wanting the ability to fly: a power it makes sense to envy but whose absence you should not mourn. What is left is attachment to yourself: a recognition of worth and the wish that it be preserved. Thus, half a notion
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
I am still working on my midlife crisis, though I think I see the way through. I need to escape the telic mindset, to cultivate a more atelic orientation. I need to learn how to be in the moment. It’s an outlook you can put to selfish use. But as it fills the emptiness of everyday life, it refuses, too, the anxiety of inconsequence in utopian schemes. It is a source of energy, focus, fullness, striving for whatever is worth striving for, to know and prize the fact that you are striving for it now.