The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science
Rate it:
Open Preview
Kindle Notes & Highlights
Read between June 14 - June 25, 2021
1%
Flag icon
Among the isles of Greece there is a certain island, insula nobilis et amoena, which Aristotle knew well. It lies on the Asian side, between the Troad and the Mysian coast, and far into its bosom, by the little town of Pyrrha, runs a broad and sheltered lagoon. D’Arcy Wentworth Thompson, On Aristotle as a biologist (1913)
2%
Flag icon
It was said that Aristotle used to walk the Lyceum’s shady paths and that, as he did so, he talked. He talked about the proper constitution of the city: the dangers of tyranny – and of democracy too. And of how Tragedy purifies through pity and fear. He analysed the meaning of the Good, to agathon, and spoke of how humans should spend their lives. He set his students logical puzzles and then demanded that they reconsider the nature of fundamental reality. He spoke in terse syllogisms and then illustrated his meaning with endless lists of things. He began his lectures with the most abstract ...more
2%
Flag icon
His students would have regarded him with awe and, perhaps, a little fear. Some of his sayings suggest an acid tongue: ‘The roots of education are bitter, but the fruit is sweet.’ ‘Educated men are as superior to uneducated as the living are to the dead.’ Of a rival philosopher he said: ‘It would be a shame for me to keep quiet if Xenocrates is still talking.’ There is a description too, and it isn’t an attractive one. It’s of a dandy who wore lots of rings, dressed rather too well and fussed about with his hair. Asked why people seek beauty in others he replied: ‘That’s a question only a ...more
2%
Flag icon
Aristotle was an intellectual omnivore, a glutton for information and ideas. But the subject he loved most was biology. In his works the ‘study of nature’ springs to life for he turns to describing and explaining the plants and animals that, in all their variety, fill our world.* To be sure, some philosophers and physicians had dabbled in biology before him, but Aristotle gave much of his life to it. He was the first to do so. He mapped the territory. He invented the science. You could argue that invented science itself.
2%
Flag icon
But most of Aristotle’s science isn’t descriptive at all: it’s answers to questions, hundreds of them.
2%
Flag icon
Diogenes Laertius, the gossiping biographer who recorded Aristotle’s looks (five centuries after his death), said, ‘In the sphere of natural science he surpassed all other philosophers in the investigation of causes, so that even the most insignificant phenomena were explained by him.’ His explanations penetrate his philosophy. There is a sense in which his philosophy is biology – in which he devised his ontology and epistemology just to explain how animals work. Ask Aristotle: what, fundamentally, exists? He would not say – as a modern biologist might – ‘go ask a physicist’; he’d point to a ...more
3%
Flag icon
The science that Aristotle began has grown great, but his descendants have all but forgotten him. Throw a stone in some boroughs of London, Paris, New York or San Francisco and you’ll be sure to hit a molecular biologist on the head. But, having felled your biologist, ask her – what did Aristotle do? You will be met with – at best – a puzzled frown. Yet Gesner, Aldrovandi, Vesalius, Fabricius, Redi, Leeuwenhoek, Harvey, Ray, Linnaeus, Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire père et fils and Cuvier – to name just a few of many – read him. They absorbed the very structure of his thought. And so his thought ...more
3%
Flag icon
I like to think that a scientist may, just occasionally, see in Aristotle’s writings something that the philologists and philosophers have missed. For sometimes he speaks directly to any biologist’s heart, as when he tells us why we should study living things. We must imagine him in the marble colonnades of the Lyceum, addressing a group of truculent students. He gestures towards a mound of ink-stained cuttlefish decomposing in the Attic sun. Pick one, he says, cut, open, look. ‘. . .?’ Exasperated, he tries to make them understand: So we should not, like children, react with disgust to the ...more
4%
Flag icon
Perhaps, then, what marks the physiologoi as early scientists is not so much the use of naturalistic explanations for the mysteries that the world presents, as rational ones. They believed that wisdom did not merely have to be received, but that ideas were worth debating and, if need be, discarding. They argued with each other and those who came before them; they were ambitious for their ideas. Here is Heraclitus (fl. 500 BC) evaluating some of his predecessors: ‘great learning does not teach sense: for otherwise it would have taught Hesiod and Pythagoras and again Xenophanes and Hecataeus’. ...more
4%
Flag icon
Empedocles (c. 492–432 BC) was an exception. A Sicilian of noble birth, he was an orator, poet, politician, healer and charismatic seer. In the opening lines of his religious poem Purifications, he presents himself as an immortal god and describes how, when he enters a city, thousands flock to him requesting cures and oracles – requests which he satisfied, on at least on one occasion, by raising the dead. Jesus with an ego, then, or Zarathustra with attitude, but he was also an immensely influential natural philosopher who wrote On Nature, several thousand lines of verse containing, among ...more
4%
Flag icon
Hippocrates (fl. 450 BC?) was going to school. In the plateia of Kos town there is a plane, ancient and gnarled, that is – so the label claims – the very tree under which the adult Hippocrates once sat dispensing cures and wisdom. It can’t be the same tree, but then the medical writings that are attributed to Hippocrates probably aren’t his either. Parts of the Corpus Hippocraticum, a medley of some sixty works, are old enough to have been written by him or his pupils, but others date from around the first century AD. Most of them are sober, professional texts that give naturalistic ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
5%
Flag icon
He was born in 384 BC in Stagira, a coastal town not far from modern Thessalonika. His father, Nicomachus, was an Asclepiad – part priest, part physician. No common quack, he was physician royal to Amyntas III of Macedon. This is less impressive than it sounds. Macedon was a semi-barbaric backwoods state with a court to match. At the age of seventeen Aristotle was sent to Plato’s Academy in Athens. He remained there, as student and teacher, for nearly twenty years. By the time the teenaged Aristotle arrived at Athens to sit at Plato’s feet, the tradition of natural philosophy, no more than two ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
5%
Flag icon
‘Socrates called philosophy down from the heavens, placed it in cities, introduced it into families, and obliged it to examine into life and morals, good and evil.’ That was Cicero’s judgement – and he meant it as praise.
5%
Flag icon
Plato shared the Pythagoreans’ fascination with geometry, and The Timaeus contains one of the first attempts to use mathematics to describe the natural world. ‘Let no one ignorant of geometry enter here’ is said to have been inscribed on the lintel of the Academy’s entrance; the same phrase is written above the swipecard-sealed doors of any Department of Physics, even if you can’t see it. Then, too, if Plato’s science is barely distinguishable from theology so, to judge by the pronouncements of some physicists, is modern science: ‘If we discover a complete theory, it would be the ultimate ...more
6%
Flag icon
Aristotle would turn his back on his teacher’s idealism and see the world, our world, for what it is: a thing that is beautiful and so worth studying in its own right. He would approach it with the humility and seriousness that it deserves. He would observe it with care and be unafraid to dirty his hands doing so. He would become the first true scientist. That he made of himself this after having been taught by one of the most persuasive intellects of all time – that is the mystery of Aristotle. All he ever said by way of explanation is: ‘piety requires us to honour truth above our friends’.
6%
Flag icon
Yet, if D’Arcy Thompson is right, it was on Lesbos that Aristotle began the great work of charting, and understanding, the world of living things. It may have been a conversation; a chance comment that prompted an excited reply. And then more talk, and yet more, until a vision of the whole enormous, daunting, thrilling thing emerged. It’s an appealing thought – that biology began so. And it’s not an implausible one. For when Aristotle went to Lesbos it seems that he had at least one other philosopher to talk to: a man who would become one of his closest friends and who would inherit his ...more
7%
Flag icon
It is a charming conceit to think of the two philosophers strolling in an olive grove, not too far from the Lagoon, dividing up the natural world between them; agreeing, as any two scientists might, to collaborate rather than compete: ‘You do the plants, I’ll do the animals – and together we’ll lay the foundations of biology.’ Charming, but too simple. Theophrastus wrote books about animals and Aristotle wrote at least one about plants; but in both cases they have been lost. That botanists look to one as the founder of their science and zoologists the other is, it seems, largely due to the ...more
7%
Flag icon
This is how Thompson put it: ‘He will be a lucky naturalist who shall go some day and spend a quiet summer by that calm lagoon, find there all the natural wealth, * and have around his feet the creatures that Aristotle knew and loved.’ I have done so. He is right.
7%
Flag icon
TO ASSERT THAT ARISTOTLE was a scientist is to suppose that we can recognize one. Sociologists and philosophers have long tried to get the creature in their sights, with indifferent results, for so diverse are their activities and preoccupations that it is hard to find a definition that will embrace them all yet exclude astrologers. Scientists, who are much less exercised about definitions, simply recognize their kin but, if pressed, might offer something like ‘A scientist is someone who seeks, by systematic investigation, to understand experienced reality.’ This definition, a generous one, ...more
7%
Flag icon
All men, by nature, desire to know. An indication of this is the delight that we take in our senses; for even apart from their usefulness they are loved for themselves; and, above all others, the sense of sight . . . The reason is that this, most of all the senses, acquaints us with, and brings to light, many differences between things. Aristotle does not mean ‘know’ just in the sense of ‘understand’; he also means ‘perceive’. Thus in the first instance we should read his words as the claim that men take pleasure in the exercise of their senses, and the reason why they do so is because it ...more
7%
Flag icon
To get from perception to wisdom, Aristotle gives us a hierarchy of understanding. When we perceive something, he says, we acquire a memory of it. And many memories of a given kind of thing allow us to generalize about it. Memories of Socrates and Plato, say, allow us to generalize about ‘men’. This is Aristotle opening another front contra Plato who held that we are born with all the knowledge that we have – indeed all the knowledge that we could have, that is, all the knowledge in the world. It’s just that, unfortunately, we have forgotten it; our task, then, is to retrieve that knowledge. ...more
8%
Flag icon
We have to begin, he says, with the phainomena –whence comes our ‘phenomena’, but perhaps the best translation is ‘appearances’, for he means by this not only what he sees with his own eyes, but also what other people have seen, and their opinions about it. He favours reports from ‘wise’ and ‘reputable’ people. He’s conscious that one man can’t see everything; sometimes you just have to trust what other people tell you (the Greeks inherited huge astronomical catalogues from Babylon and Egypt).
8%
Flag icon
The way in which Aristotle deals with the last of these questions – the talking heads – is instructive. Many people, he says, believe that a struck-off head can talk, and they cite Homer in support. Also, he says, there is an apparently credible description of just such a case. In Caria (Anatolia) a priest belonging to the cult of Zeus Hoplosmios was decapitated. The grounded head named its murderer as one Cerides. A Cerides was accordingly found and put on trial. Aristotle does not comment on the fate of the man, nor even on the possible miscarriage of justice, but he dismisses the story on ...more
9%
Flag icon
IN HIS ZOOLOGICAL WORKS Aristotle mentions the following mammals: ailouros (cat), alōpēx (fox), arktos (bear), aspalax (Mediterranean mole), arouraios mys (field mouse), bous/tauros (oxen), dasypous/lagos (hare), ekhinos (hedgehog), elaphos/prox (deer), eleios (dormouse), enydris (otter), galē (beech marten), ginnos (ginny), hinnos (hinny), hippos (horse), hys (pig), hystrix (porcupine), iktis (weasel), kapros (boar), kastōr (beaver), kyōn (dog), leōn (Asian lion), lykos (wolf), lynx (lynx), mys (mouse), mygalē (water shrew), nykteris (bat), oïs/krios/probaton (sheep), onos (ass), oreus ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
9%
Flag icon
Where does Aristotle’s exotic zoology come from? He was hardly ever out of sight of the Aegean Sea, so he could not have collected it himself. The Roman encyclopaedist Pliny the Elder gave an answer. As so often with Pliny’s assertions, it has a fantastical air. He said that Alexander the Great supplied it. King Alexander the Great, inflamed with a desire for discovering the natures of animals, entrusted this task to Aristotle, a man outstanding in every department of knowledge. Several thousand men in the whole region of Asia and Greece were put under his command – all those who made their ...more
9%
Flag icon
Aristotle was summoned to the Macedonian court. He had reason enough to go. Macedon was, after all, home, and it was no longer the backwater that he had left behind nearly a quarter of a century previously. Amyntas was long dead; Philip II had succeeded to the Macedonian throne, had raised an army and was flexing his military muscles. In Athens, Demosthenes warned the citizenry, in ever more apocalyptic tones, of the danger brewing on their doorstep. They ignored him – to their cost. Philip wanted a tutor for his son: someone to rub the rough edges off the boy and give him the philosophical ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
9%
Flag icon
In 336 Philip was murdered. Alexander became king. He began by reducing Thebes, second among Greece’s cities, to rubble. In a letter Aristotle counsels him to be a leader to the Greeks and to look after them as if they were ‘friends or relatives’, but Alexander sold Thebes’ citizens into slavery. He later crucified all of Gaza’s men. That was a bit more Aristotelian: in the same letter he tells Alexander to be a despot to barbarians and to ‘treat them as if they were beasts or plants’. As the young general rampaged across the known world, he carried with him a copy of the Iliad in Aristotle’s ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
9%
Flag icon
PLINY’S STORY IS charming. Alexander, no mere kohl-eyed sensualist or megalomaniacal conqueror, loves plants and animals too, and, recalling his old tutor’s interests, affectionately lays the biological booty of an empire at his feet. Writing a century or two later, Athenaeus says that Alexander gave Aristotle 800 talents for his research, and so turns the King into a Macedonian National Science Foundation. There is a whiff of romance about these tales. Eight hundred talents was several times Macedon’s annual GDP; and in his biological works Aristotle says nothing about subsidies, a zoo nor ...more
9%
Flag icon
It is also clear that Aristotle got some of his exotic zoology from travel books. Ctesias of Cnidus, a fifth-century Greek physician to the Persian court, wrote several books about Persia and India that Aristotle felt he could neither ignore nor trust. None of these kinds [genē] of animals [live-bearing tetrapods, i.e. mammals] has a double row of teeth. Well, there is one, if Ctesias is to be believed. He claims that a beast that the Indians call the martikhōras has a triple row of teeth, resembles a lion in size, is just as shaggy and has the same sort of feet. It has a face and ears like a ...more
14%
Flag icon
Most of the recombinants were unfit and perished, so we see only the survivors today. Many early natural philosophers, Simplicius remarks, had this idea. That, if true, is remarkable, for it suggests that in Aristotle’s time the idea of selection as a source of order was a commonplace. Certainly Epicurus, a generation younger than Aristotle, gave an even more elaborate selection-based cosmogeny than did Empedocles – at least he did if Lucretius’ Epicurean verses are to be relied on.
14%
Flag icon
His arguments are fascinating, for some of them have been used against the theory of evolution by natural selection. (1) Spontaneous events are rare, but the signature of genuinely purposeful events is that they are common: teeth always come up in exactly the same way. This is a probabilistic argument for the existence of a purposeful agent and, like all such arguments, it is wrong, for selection can regularly produce order from disorder.* Admittedly, Empedocles helps Aristotle to this conclusion by making his cosmogonies indeterminate: ‘[sometimes] it may happen to run one way, but often it ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
15%
Flag icon
‘Every part of the body is for some action: so what the body as a composite whole is for is a multifaceted action.’ And although Aristotle’s explorations of these profound truths are delightfully detailed and endlessly ingenious it appears that he has impaled himself on the horns of a dilemma. He sees, as Socrates and Plato did before him, the evidence of purpose writ across the face of the world; sees too that material forces alone cannot explain it, but refuses to yield to the expedient of a cosmic designer. So the question remains: from where do plan and purpose in nature come? Aristotle’s ...more
15%
Flag icon
Plato’s theory of Forms is the ancestor of all species of idealism. Modern scientists are generally realists and so will find it incomprehensible or bizarre. So did Aristotle. He wanted to explain the features of the physical world. But, if Forms are eternal and static how then, he asks, can they actually do anything? And what does it mean to say that the physical world ‘participates’ in the world of Forms? And if a Form is merely a mental conception, then does not any one physical object have as many Forms as ways that you can think about it? And if a Form exists for any given physical ...more
15%
Flag icon
Aristotle believes that the nature of a living thing, or at least the most important part of it, is in fact its form – if not its Form. The term he uses for ‘form’ is the term that Plato used, eidos. It is one of the most vital organs of his thought. Aristotle holds that any sensible object is a compound of form (eidos) and matter (hylē). One can speak of ‘form’ and ‘matter’ in the abstract, but in practice they’re actually inseparable. To explain what he means Aristotle appeals to various metaphors. If wax is hylē, then eidos is the impression made in it by a signet ring. In its most general ...more
15%
Flag icon
However, when he applies the term to the world of living things, he uses it in several distinct, but related, senses. The first biological sense in which Aristotle uses eidos is close to the English meaning of ‘form’ – as the appearance of an animal. His word for a taxon of animals is genos (pl. genē) – which I translate as ‘kind’. Some genē are small – the sparrow kind; others are large – the bird kind. So when he wants to describe the features that make a sparrow a sparrow rather than a crane, or a bird a bird rather than a fish, he speaks of its eidos.
15%
Flag icon
Which brings us to the second sense of eidos – as the fundamental unit of biodiversity, that is, close to what we mean by ‘species’. Indeed, the traditional Latin translation of eidos is precisely species, just as genus is of genos.* One could, then, rewrite the above passage as: ‘There are many species of fishes and birds.’
16%
Flag icon
Indeed, there’s a third sense in which Aristotle uses eidos. It’s related to the other two, but goes much deeper, and is much more surprising. It’s the appearance of an organism, but – if this is not too paradoxical – its appearance when it cannot yet be seen. It is the ‘information’ or the ‘formula’ which was transmitted to it by its parents, from which it built itself in the egg or womb, and which it will, in turn, transmit to its progeny. It is in this sense that Aristotle thinks that the nature of a thing resides primarily in its form. To speak of eidos as ‘information’ risks anachronism. ...more
16%
Flag icon
Aristotle considers how a woodcarver might explain his art. He clearly wouldn’t just talk about the wood – that’s merely the matter out of which it’s built. Nor would he just talk about his axe and auger – they’re merely tools. Nor would he just talk about the strokes that he makes – that’s mere technique. No, if he is really to convey the origin of the thing he’s making, he has to talk about the idea that he had when he began his work – the process by which it will unfold in his hands, its final design and ultimate purpose – he must talk about its eidos. In the same way, when a scientist ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
16%
Flag icon
The whole problem was that none of his predecessors saw that natures could be, should be, understood in several different ways. Our hearts beat – but not just because of chemistry; nor just to keep us alive; nor just because one grew in our embryonic torsos; nor even just because our parents had hearts too; rather, our hearts beat because of all of these things. All these kinds of causes complement each other, indeed, are deeply intertwined. Or so Aristotle argues in a famous methodological dictum known as the ‘four causes’. But ‘cause’ isn’t quite right: ‘four questions’ or ‘four kinds of ...more
16%
Flag icon
The efficient (or moving) cause is an account of the mechanics of movement and change. It is now the domain of developmental biology and neurophysiology. The material cause is an account of the matter – the stuff – of which animals are made, and their properties. It is now the domain of modern biochemistry and physiology. The formal cause is an account of the information transmitted that any creature received from its parents, and that is responsible for the features that it shares with other members of its species – that is, the subject matter of genetics. The final cause is teleology, the ...more
16%
Flag icon
Plato’s fans – he still has some – are particularly prone to viewing Aristotle as his teacher’s epigone. That can be accomplished only by studiously ignoring how Aristotle transformed Plato’s ideas. As a student Darwin read, and enjoyed, Paley’s Natural Theology and may have even acquired from it his keen sense of the design displayed by living things. Yet who would call Darwin a Paleyite? Calling Aristotle a Platonist is like that.
16%
Flag icon
Aristotle not only produced a new system of explanation, but also applied it. His predecessors viewed the world as if from Olympus. It lay far below them blurred by distance or obscured entirely by mist, and speculation filled in what they could not see. Aristotle, however, went down to the shore. He observed, applied his causes to his observations and wove them together in the books that make up his Great Course in Zoology: The Parts of Animals, The Length and Shortness of Life, Youth & Old Age, Life & Death, The Soul, The Generation of Animals, The Movement of Animals and The Progression of ...more
16%
Flag icon
The beauty of living things arises from their endless variety, the sense that they give of unity within diversity, and the intricacy of their relations. In the face of nature’s munificence it’s all too easy to surrender to an inarticulate sense of the numinous connectedness of things, or else let it all surge by in a kaleidoscopic blur. Haeckel looked down upon the coral gardens of Al-Tur and babbled of the Magical Hesperides; Darwin entered the Mata Atlântica at Rio and discovered devotion – faced with a rainforest, anyone can go weak at the knees. If, however, we wish to understand the ...more
20%
Flag icon
EVERY SCIENTIST HAS a conception of what constitutes ‘good science’. It is a sense, as firmly held as it is poorly articulated, of which causal claims are sound and which aren’t. It’s not, of course, that scientists necessarily agree on the soundness of any given claim. If you have ever contemplated the reviews of a manuscript, submitted with such hope to Nature or Science (for at the gates to these journals hope truly does spring eternal), you will know that your peers’ notions of what constitute sound causal claims are often very different from your own and really quite confused. Aristotle ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
20%
Flag icon
ORGANON MEANS ‘TOOL’ or ‘instrument’.* It’s the title often given to six of Aristotle’s books. It’s an apt one for they are tools for the production of knowledge. One of these books, the Posterior Analytics, contains his scientific method. Aristotle distinguishes the rules for debating opinions from the rules for constructing scientific explanations. The first he called ‘dialectic’, the latter ‘demonstration’ (the Greek is apodeixis). By ‘demonstration’ he means exactly what a modern scientist means when he says, ‘we have demonstrated that A is the cause of B’ – that is, he and his ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
22%
Flag icon
For all its limitations, Aristotle’s theory of demonstration is a genuine scientific method. It is part of ours. Scientists may quarrel about methodology but they also agree about a lot. They understand the domain of science: the kinds of things it investigates. They understand how it delimits things and problems and investigates them piecemeal rather than trying to study and answer everything. They understand the reciprocal role of theory and evidence and the distinction between hypothesis and fact. They understand that science begins with induction to give generalizations from observations ...more
26%
Flag icon
THE TRADITIONAL GREEK conception of soul was Homer’s. Patroclus falls at Troy and his disembodied soul takes wing for the House of Hades. Perhaps this explains why the Greek name for a butterfly is the same as that for ‘soul’ – psychē – for, as the soul flees a corpse at death, so a butterfly clambers from its chrysalis. In The Phaedo Plato elaborates the traditional theory. The soul is no longer merely something lost when we die; it reasons and regulates the body’s desires while we are alive. Now it is Socrates who is dying. His soul, too, will leave the body in which it is trapped and travel ...more
26%
Flag icon
Aristotle wrote a whole book about the soul, de Anima, or The Soul. Devoid of Platonic moralizing, it is resolutely scientific in tone: Some types of knowledge may be especially fine and worthwhile for their precision or because their objects have greater value and elicit greater wonder. It is for both these reasons that we should treat the study of the soul as one of extreme importance. However its investigation seems to be of special importance for truth as a whole and the study of nature in particular. For souls are the principle of animal life. This, to us, is a very strange, even suspect, ...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
26%
Flag icon
I have argued that, when Aristotle speaks of the ‘form’ or ‘formal nature’ of a creature, he often means the information required to order matter into a creature of a given kind. This interpretation is based not only on the various analogies he gives (imprints in wax; letters and syllables), but also on the fact that forms are present even when they are invisible. They are somehow present in an animal’s seed and are responsible for the development of the embryo and the appearance and functions of the adult. So an animal’s soul is its form, albeit under particular circumstances: If we must say ...more
26%
Flag icon
‘actuality’ – entelekheia. It is this word, a bit of Aristotelian jargon, that is most distinctive about his theory of the soul. He often uses it in opposition to ‘potentiality’ – dynamis. The opposition runs deep into his physical theory. Any change, in Aristotle’s view, is the actualization of a potential. Thus when he says that the soul is an actuality, he’s stressing the fact that it’s something that previously existed only potentially; that it’s something that comes into being from something else. When combined with the claim that the soul of a living thing is ‘its form in its body’, it ...more
« Prev 1