Poetics
Rate it:
Open Preview
Read between February 4 - February 18, 2023
4%
Flag icon
Philosophy was the last form of literature to reach maturity in classical Greece, but with its arrival literature became for the first time reflective, and conscious of itself.
4%
Flag icon
Both Plato’s and Aristotle’s works contain reflections on the purpose and value of literature. Both philosophers are keenly interested in the relationship between literature and morality, and because they have different conceptions of morality they have different attitudes to literature.
5%
Flag icon
Aristotle, however, devoted a self-standing work, the Poetics, to the issues that Plato had discussed in fragmented fashion. His brief treatise stands out, therefore, as the first surviving work devoted to literary criticism, and indeed the first essay in the broader field of aesthetics.
5%
Flag icon
The Greek word poiesis (literally ‘making’), as used by Aristotle, has both a narrower and a wider scope than the English word ‘poetry’.
5%
Flag icon
Aristotle’s insights transcend the boundaries of ancient Greek culture and can be applied to creative writing of many ages and many nations.
5%
Flag icon
Aristotle provides a prism through which different kinds of imaginative writing may be viewed and evaluated.
5%
Flag icon
The Poetics concentrates on a single art form: tragedy.
5%
Flag icon
tragedy was the most fully developed literary product of the time.
5%
Flag icon
While seeking to lay bare the essence of tragedy, Aristotle was able to expose, through his close inspection of this single genre, some of the basic principles operative in the creative process itself.
9%
Flag icon
Aristotle defines tragedy in the following terms: Tragedy is a representation of an action of a superior kind—grand, and complete in itself—presented in embellished language, in distinct forms in different parts, performed by actors rather than told by a narrator, effecting, through pity and fear, the purification of such emotions. (1449b24 ff.)
11%
Flag icon
Aristotle insists that in tragedy the most important element of all is story: the characters are created for the sake of the story, and not the other way round.
15%
Flag icon
The poet’s job, Aristotle tells us, is not to relate what actually happened, but rather the kind of thing that would happen, either necessarily or probably.
17%
Flag icon
drama teaches us in a manner that motivates us, in a way that chill moral truisms do not.
20%
Flag icon
The Italian humanist Ludovico Castelvetro published in 1576 a text of the Poetics with a translation and commentary. He blew up Aristotle’s remarks on unity and scale into a doctrine of the Three Unities, of time, place, and action.
20%
Flag icon
The principles he set out could only dubiously claim the backing of Aristotle, but they had a great influence on the classical French tragedies of Corneille, and through him, on English Restoration dramatists such as John Dryden.
42%
Flag icon
Tragedy is a representation not of persons but of action and life, and happiness and unhappiness consist in action. The point is action, not character:
42%
Flag icon
it is their moral status that gives people the character they have, but it is their actions that make them happy or unhappy.
42%
Flag icon
the most important devices that tragedy uses to affect the emotions are parts of the story—namely, reversals and discoveries.
44%
Flag icon
The limit that is set by the nature of the subject is this: the longer the story, the grander the scale, provided it remains comprehensible as a whole.
44%
Flag icon
If the presence or absence of something makes no discernible difference, then it is no part of the whole.
44%
Flag icon
poetry utters universal truths, history particular statements.
45%
Flag icon
what is possible is credible.
45%
Flag icon
* These effects occur above all when things come about unexpectedly but at the same time consequentially.
45%
Flag icon
even chance events are found more astonishing when they seemed to have happened for a purpose.
46%
Flag icon
Discovery, as the term implies, is a change from ignorance to knowledge, and thus to either love or hate, on the part of those destined for good or bad fortune.
47%
Flag icon
good men should not be shown passing from good fortune to bad, for that evokes not fear or pity, but outrage. Nor should depraved men be shown passing from bad fortune to good—this indeed is the least tragic of all: it has none of the appropriate features, evoking neither pity nor fear nor even basic human sympathy. Finally, a very wicked man should not be shown passing from good fortune to bad: this may evoke basic human sympathy, but neither pity nor fear.
48%
Flag icon
The story should be put together in such a way that even without seeing the play a person hearing the series of events should feel dread and pity.
48%
Flag icon
The effect that some producers try to achieve is not so much fear as horror: that has nothing at all to do with tragedy.
49%
Flag icon
it is no good for a character to be courageous if the courage or intelligence is expressed in a way that is not appropriate
50%
Flag icon
Clearly, the explication* of a story should issue from the story itself, and not from a deus ex machina