More on this book
Community
Kindle Notes & Highlights
Read between
April 14 - April 23, 2024
Both outside the academy and within, American readers turned to the Übermensch as a concept essential for understanding modern selfhood. Whereas popular authors, journalists, and social reformers typically cast the figure as an aggrandized self at war with society, philosophers, humanists, and social scientists within the academy understood the Übermensch as the self at war with itself. While few scholars thought it a salutary image of modern self-hood, they nevertheless recognized its value for testing the moral discourses of romanticism, naturalism, liberalism, and pragmatism.
In all three interpretations, the enemies of the Übermensch were the retrograde aspects of modern life: laissez-faire economics, the American plutocracy, repressive sexuality and gender roles, and the “slave morality” of bourgeois culture.
Once he had sufficiently dethroned Demos, he went on to attack Christian charity. According to Mencken, the Übermensch had the perspicacity to recognize, and the courage to accept, that Christian charity weakened the “race,” for it “maintain[ed] the useless at the expense of the strong.”
In order to conclude that “Nietzsche undoubtedly foresaw and welcomed the Super woman,” appreciative female readers were inspired by the vision of the perfected woman as “the mother of the transfigured man of the future.”18 However, fighting such an image of glorified motherhood is precisely what drew Margaret Sanger to the Übermensch. Sanger discovered in Nietzsche’s thought both a critical philosophy and an aspirational idea for achieving a woman’s right to bodily self-sovereignty. In her speeches and writings, she employed the Übermensch to critique the bankrupt Western morality that
...more
Royce observed that modern reformers had discovered in Nietzsche’s thought a source of and justification for their overpowering iconoclastic individualism that threatened to tear the bonds of ethical and communal affiliation. However, he contended that the popular view of Nietzsche’s Übermensch as a tireless crusader against social conventions, which was popularized by Shaw, London, and Mencken and bandied about in the popular press, misunderstood Nietzsche’s broader vision. The “modern agitator,” the “typically restless child of our age,” noted Royce, believed that Nietzsche’s philosophy
...more
he recognized in Nietzsche another philosopher who emphasized the important role temperament plays in determining one’s philosophical views and commitments. But it was likely James’s agreement with Nietzsche that philosophy is a confession of the author’s temperament that made it so awkward to find himself advancing a view of the nature of moral personhood strikingly similar to that of a philosopher whom he regarded as “pathetic and diseased.”
In his unpublished notes on ethics, James considered the rivalries between what he referred to as individual “high mindedness” and social “prudence.” While both make their contributions to society, he wondered whether it is a particular “high minded” type who ultimately propels humanity forward. He described him as the solitary, restless, immoderate “gentleman” who marries his private visions with personal sacrifice and social reality. James wrote,“We stumble on; the übermenschen plant a foot where there is no certain hold; & in the struggle that follows, the whole of us get dragged up after a
...more
According to James (and finding confirmation in Nietzsche), there are no absolute ideal types of saintliness; virtues are relative to the beholder.“There is, in short, no absoluteness in the excellence of sainthood.”46 But more important, empiricism shows that while the saintly type might appeal in theory, in the real world we make ourselves “saintly” saints at our peril. James thus encouraged religious moderns to bring their religion a bit closer to earth.
In the early 1910s and 1920s, the New Humanists were among the most visible and vocal opponents of Nietzsche in the academy. The Übermensch surfaces repeatedly as their bête noire—a symbol for the degenerative impulses in romanticism and naturalism that they believed plagued modern life.
He argued that Nietzsche’s vision of self-overcoming would lead inexorably into an immoral self-abandonment—an abnegation both of the self and of the traditional anchors that bound the individual to eternal truths. Whereas Royce perceived self-overcoming to be a strengthening of the self and one’s moral resolve in an uncertain universe, Babbitt interpreted it to be a weakening of the self by succumbing to the whirl of modern lawlessness in the realm of ethics and aesthetics.
In their common efforts to identify Rousseau as the origin and Nietzsche as the consequence of the romantic revolt against classicism, the critical New Humanists failed to notice that the two thinkers were awkward representatives of the alpha and omega of naturalist and instrumental tendencies in modern thought. By linking Nietzsche with Rousseau and Rousseau with an unbridled celebration of nature, they overlooked Nietzsche’s sustained critiques of the French thinker—critiques that anticipated their own attacks on naturalism. Beginning with The Birth of Tragedy and culminating in The Twilight
...more
Yet while the New Humanists argued that modern romanticism had a French lineage stemming back to Rousseau, Santayana argued instead that it was the most recent expression of a German idealistic egotism that dated to the Protestant Reforma-tion. Echoing the sentiments of early twentieth-century American Catholic thinkers and clergy, Santayana contended that German Protestantism was an unbridled celebration of individual will and a denial of the authority of the Gospels. He argued that German thinkers from Goethe and Kant down to Nietzsche had inherited Protestantism’s rejection of
...more
Although Santayana viewed art as vital to human experience, he believed that it contributed to life only if it was the work of the “trained” artist who had ensured that the lines of a poem or the brushstrokes of a painting corresponded to “prescribed” standards of aesthetic form. In Santayana’s estimation, this submission to externally sanctioned ideals was reprehensible to the German philosopher: “To be trained is to be tamed and harnessed, an accession of power detestable to Nietzsche.”
Drawing on their prewar critiques of the romantic origins of modern relativism and its dangerous consequences for civilization, Irving Babbitt and Paul Elmer More argued that Nietzsche’s frenzied irrationalism and celebration of will-to-power had spiraled into German racialist superiority and a “lust of empire.”
One of the strongest objections came from William James’s brother-in-law, William Mackintire Salter, himself a prolific writer and speaker on ethics, as well as an early follower of Felix Adler, the German-Jewish founder of the Ethical Culture movement, and the leader of the Society for Ethical Culture of Chicago. Salter, once an aspiring Congregational minister who rejected Christian orthodoxy and turned to Unitarianism before his faith in the “solid grounds for distinctive Christian faith” fully gave way, discovered in Nietzsche a fellow antifoundationalist ethicist who took a higher
...more
Now the excessive worldliness of German Protestantism appeared to be too much of a good thing, as German theologians and clergy saw themselves as functionaries of the German state and had politicized Protestant theology by making it serviceable to the nation’s military mission.
Cognizant that the war had justly soured the US perception of German political life, the economist Simon Nelson Patten sought to rescue the German welfare-state model, which he believed was still worthy of emulation. In contrast to the view of the German Übermensch as a disintegrative social force, Patten offered a countervision of a “super race,” as reflected in Germany’s mechanization, efficiency, and social morality.91 According to Patten, the Übermensch, properly understood, represented a bridge between the American conception of freedom and the German regard for social organization. He
...more
figures as diverse as Emma Goldman, H. L. Mencken, and Randolph Bourne mined Nietzsche’s texts for his critique of Judeo-Christian asceticism and moral psychology as they attempted to come to terms with the lingering influence of Puritanism on modern American thought.
Emerson’s longing for a society of “complete” men and women, his belief that the poet is the full realization of the thinker and the artist in man, helps explain why American socialists and Progressives who cared deeply about social solidarity insisted on Nietzsche as the exemplar of the philosopher-poet.
Even strict materialist socialists who focused on bread-and-butter labor issues could turn to Nietzsche for the inspiration to imagine themselves laboring toward a new poetics of humanity. Nowhere do we better see this than with the radical West Indian–American writer Hubert Harrison, founder of the “New Negro” movement. An avid reader of Nietzsche—from his time as a postal worker and freelance editorialist and lecturer in his early twenties through his involvement in the Socialist Party, as a lecturer at the Ferrer Modern School (a hothouse for American Nietzscheanism),19 and into the 1920s
...more
John Gould Fletcher, the imagist poet and essayist, first came across Nietzsche’s Zarathustra while he was a student at Harvard: “All through 1904–5 I absorbed it in large doses, reading Nietzsche day after day at the Harvard Union, and dreaming about the superman at night.” This intimacy with Nietzsche drew him away from the Christianity of his boyhood and toward poetry, as even the godless “must believe in something” ; if there were indeed no God, then it would be up to the poets to create new images of the possible.
Taking delight in discussing Nietzsche’s ideas, the radicals also treasured volumes of his work among their personal possessions, and his books figured prominently in their gifts to one another. In their desire to institute the collective control of the nation’s economic production, they shared a thinker who showed them that the real wealth of any commonwealth is its native intellect. Giving a Nietzsche volume to someone symbolized socialist solidarity, as Mabel Dodge Luhan demonstrated when she gave the young IWW organizer Frank Tannenbaum a copy of Nietzsche to bolster his political will as
...more
Goldman had first read selections from Nietzsche in Reitzel’s Arme Teufel, and although she was very intrigued, it was not until studying in Vienna in 1895 that she had a chance to systematically read his works. She reveled in her discovery of the “magic of [Nietzsche’s] language, the beauty of his vision, [which] carried me to undreamed-of heights.” She wanted to share with Brady her “raptures over Nietzsche.” But Brady mocked her fascination with “the great poet-philosopher,” unwilling to concede that his aristocratic radicalism might have anything to offer philosophical anarchism. They
...more
By turning to Nietzsche, these avant-garde writers were participating in the Emersonian practice of looking to Europe for intellectual models. Although Emerson had longed for an America that cultivated its own native intellect, one that no longer feasted off the remains of Europe, his Representative Men was a confession that the culture of American democracy may never pull this off.
There were plenty of European “geniuses” for Americans to turn to, but Nietzsche especially spoke to their romance with independence from institutions and their consequent anxiety of being marginalized. He helped those like Stearns, who sought intellectual freedom yet disliked its consequences: “In our national life to-day the young intellectual speedily finds that he is not wanted.”49 If genius has a history, so too does the hero worship of the alienated genius; and it is this iteration of the young intellectuals’ cult of genius that helps explain how the ground for the romance with Nietzsche
...more
Nietzsche’s own writings about genius helped flesh out the stillforming notion of the freelance thinker. He characterized genius as antagonistic to all traditional sources of authority, hence hostile to moral complacency, and he argued that society is equally hostile to it in return. However, Nietzsche also emphasized the geniality of intolerance for the genius. “Mutilation, crippling, [and] a serious deficiency in an organ offers the occasion for an uncommonly successful development of another organ,” he argued.“It is in this way one can suppose many a glittering talent to have originated.”53
...more
According to Cook, Nietzsche pushed his mind toward insanity knowingly and willingly. His madness was no accident, it was martyrdom. Nietzsche “would have been willing to pay the price had he known in advance that it was to be the loss of reason,” Cook wrote. He knew that a new world of ideas worth living for would also be worth dying for; mental death was the price.
Of all the figures Nietzsche was likened to—modern mystic, Christ, Faust, Prometheus—the one that resonated the most was Nietzsche as a present-day Hamlet. The unfulfilled longings and haunted imagination, which thrust him into madness, recalled the tragic fate that befell Shakespeare’s Danish prince. Comparing Nietzsche to Hamlet would remain a perennial feature of Nietzsche interpretation in the United States among thinkers reflecting on the perils of their enterprise.
The Hamlet-Nietzsche metaphor for genius revealed their alienation from—and ambivalence toward—the modern democratic public culture they wanted to serve and to lead. The spectacle of Nietzsche laboring in silence, and ultimately collapsing beneath the burden of his refused genius, resonated with a number of intellectuals who perceived themselves as similarly marginalized by an American culture indifferent to their ideas.
Nietzsche not only endured suffering, he theorized about it. As he wrote in Untimely Meditations (1873–76), the cultural philistine “fancies that he is himself a son of the muses and a man of culture,” while the great thinker is a seeker. The philistine thus thinks he possesses that which the true genius seeks: “a genuine, original … culture.”69 Bourne identified this as the problem of the American mind—not the cultural hostility to the critical intellect but “the uncritical hospitality of current taste.” He saw a danger in the sunny gentility that marked American cultural attitudes, which was
...more
If, as Nietzsche argued, moral language is not an expression of universal truth but rather an instrument to serve particular social functions, then it would be their role as critics of American values to investigate how, for example, modern-day Christians and laissez-faire capitalists used words as strongholds to defend or justify their religious traditions and aggrandized wealth. The young intellectuals were committed to progressive reform and cultural renewal but also to the belief that neither God nor natural law demanded that they be so. In A Preface to Politics (1913), Walter Lippmann
...more
moral indeterminacy could place heavy demands on the individual, however. Indeed, as Emma Goldman admitted, it “urges man to think.” While Goldman stressed that “perfect personality” could be realized once moderns liberate their minds from “man-made law” and “truth grown false with age,” she also insisted that they would prefer gilding their cages to breaking free of them. Though the masses would be the first to benefit from recognizing how religious and even supposedly democratic ideals espoused in American public life were instruments of internecine terror rather than divine commandments,
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
For Hubert Harrison, it was bad enough to have poverty (the result of an exploitative capitalist system) put a lock on your mind, but it was even worse to have your own religion do it. This was, in his view, the most powerful insight Nietzsche’s genealogy of the slave morality offered to African Americans. Nietzsche helped him see that African Americans especially should liberate themselves from the “dubious blessings of Christianity,” and breathe the larger air of “Freethought.” He believed, however, that they were the least likely to do so because “the church saw to it that [Christianity]
...more
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
While today it is commonplace to bewail the puritanical prudery and provincialism of American culture, the Puritans didn’t always have such a bad reputation. Only when early twentieth-century critics like Goldman, Mencken, and Bourne started to excavate the past for the historical conditions conspiring against the free intellect did the modern conception of the Puritan develop. The radicals collapsed Nietzsche’s analyses of Christian asceticism and sentimentalism into a critique of the lingering effects of Puritan psychology and piety. While the philistines treated ideas as if they were merely
...more
Her concern, though, was not simply with the modern Puritan’s denials of earthly pleasures, but rather the toll that a despiritualized Christian morality—what she referred to as the “narrow puritanic spirit” —takes on the life of the mind. “Aspirit which is absolutely blind to the simplest manifestations of life; hence stands for stagnation and decay,” she argued, can only produce an intellectual life that is fearful, wrathful, and “steeped in the densest provincialism.” Social conservatives were not its only victims. Indeed, social progressives “apparently free from religious and social
...more
In his 1917 essay “Puritanism as a Literary Force,” Mencken sought the origins of modern American literature’s didactic style, which was devoid of difficult ideas as well as literary nuance, play, or depth. His genealogy of American anti-intellectualism followed many of the same lines as Santayana’s and Brooks’s. It began with the austere, self-accusing Calvinist of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, who lost his dominance with the rise of his nineteenth-century descendant, the philistine, a “trader” or “peasant” in Mencken’s version. The philistine is at home in this world but never
...more
During the Victorian period, the old Puritanism lost its hold on individual conscience, but its zealotry remained. The once self-accusing sinners in the hands of an angry God were now self-righteous zealots on the prowl for souls to torment. Neo-Puritanism, Mencken argued, explained the modern American: His enthusiasm was not for repentance, but for what he began to call service. In brief, the national sense of energy and fitness gradually superimposed itself upon the national Puritanism, and from that marriage sprung a keen Wille zur Macht, a lusty will to power. The American Puritan, by now,
...more
Bourne agreed with Nietzsche that modern ethics had become tired expressions of nineteenth-century sentimentalism: “We have become enfeebled by humanitarianism… . Sympathy in place of justice saps the fibre of character and gives free rein to egoistic impulses.”100 Bourne concluded with Nietzsche that sympathy and selflessness do not represent the effacement of the aggrandized self but are rather expressions of it. He argued that even acts of supposed goodwill are really“will to power” strategies, for the act of giving is merely an assertion of our superiority over the person we are supposedly
...more
Drawing the line of argument straight from Nietzsche, Bourne argued that it is a mistake for his fellow critics to dismiss the Puritan’s asceticism as “unnatural,” because the entire force of the puritanical belief structure is the way it burrows into the individual’s moral psychology and becomes “secondnature.” As Bourne put it, the externalized dictates of religion over time become naturalized into the believer’s entire ethical and psychological gestalt. As a result,“the puritan becomes just as much of a naturalistic phenomenon as the most carnal sinner.”
Like Emerson and Nietzsche before him, Bourne was troubled about the prospect of inheritance always having the last word, the prospect that we are always inhibited in ways often invisible to us, either from birth or by our upbringing, so that our assertions of self are merely the rattling of our cages. Though Bourne refused to give in to the myth of the given, he argued that people internalize the dictates of society and only “dimly realize that their outward lives are largely a compulsion of social habit.” Although he insisted that “there is nothing fixed about the objects to which society
...more
Lippmann, Walling, and Bourne best expressed this enthusiasm about the parallels between Nietzsche, James, and Dewey. They praised the experimental approach to knowledge and social problems advocated by all three philosophers. And they delighted in the common argument that knowledge is created, not inherited—made, not found. The critics applied this logic to argue that historical knowledge, scientific formulas, and cultural conventions are true only insofar as they are life-affirming and heighten humankind’s sense of the possible. In addition, Nietzsche and the pragmatists stressed that man is
...more
The radicals discovered in Nietzsche an image of the apostolic thinker that reminded them of what Emerson had had in mind in “Circles” when he claimed, “Beware when the great God lets loose a thinker on this planet. Then all things are at risk.”118 Nietzsche’s model was an apostolic thinker who did not hoist himself onto the empty throne of a dead God or offer his own texts as a new New Testament, but rather posed, as Nietzsche had, the momentous question to himself and his readers: “Could you think a God?”119 What they longed for were good models of the antifoundational intellect who helped
...more
Fans young and old, male and female, pious and agnostic, from the Left and from the Right, immigrant and native born, sent letters expressing their admiration for Nietzsche. Like Hintz, they requested a picture or an autograph, or simply testified in haunting and exquisite detail how reading his philosophy transformed their views of themselves and their world. They showed how Nietzsche helped them critique the religion of their youth, the intellectual poverty of their democratic culture, and the materialism of their consumer society. They documented the media through which they had access to
...more
Nietzsche had given her justification for, and a language to articulate, her feelings of displacement and disaffection in a world that seemed content with ugly compromises. His philosophy gained traction in readers yearning for individuality as well as belonging. In their desire for self-understanding, they fashioned their own version of Nietzsche as the exemplar of individuality and a new self in that image.
Nietzsche’s more dominant appeal lay in how he sanctioned readers’ feelings of radical otherness—feelings that traversed ethnic, racial, class, and gender divides. As Werner Sollors reminds us, “In America, casting oneself as an outsider may in fact be considered a dominant cultural trait.”
That Nietzsche’s philosophy could shrink the distance between German and American culture was the last thing on many of his American readers’ minds. Though they were reading Nietzsche in the United States, they never thought his philosophy would find refuge here, nor did they desire it. They simply wanted more of Nietzsche, more of the German pathos of distance, more of his philosophy with which to shield themselves from the crude, anti-intellectual mob mentality of American life.
Even for those who came to Nietzsche with a sense of being human, all too human, he showed them a pathos of distance from everyday values—whether of the church, the marketplace, or the civics lesson—that helped them sharpen their sense of distinction in themselves, enabling them to feel their own particularity. And the letter shows how Nietzsche’s readers yearned for a philosophy that harmonized thinking and doing.
Kaufmann also employed Nietzsche to address what he regarded as the impoverished status of philosophy in midcentury American life. In his estimation, the “parting of the ways” in transatlantic philosophy that split continental European and English-speaking philosophers into two antagonistic groups hampered the proper reception of Nietzsche in American universities and damaged moral inquiry in general.7 Rather than ascribe Nietzsche to either the Continental or the Anglo-analytic tradition, Kaufmann sought to extend the reach of Nietzsche’s significance by demonstrating how his philosophy
...more
Scholars generally agree that in order to distance Nietzsche from Nazism, Kaufmann transformed Nietzsche into a charming and inoffensive salonfähig existentialist, erasing the darker elements of his philosophy of power and neutralizing his attacks on liberal ideals.