The Structure of Scientific Revolutions
Rate it:
Open Preview
Read between December 26, 2014 - January 11, 2015
7%
Flag icon
Against Method (1975)
13%
Flag icon
Normal science, the activity in which most scientists inevitably spend almost all their time, is predicated on the assumption that the scientific community knows what the world is like.
13%
Flag icon
Copernicus, Newton, Lavoisier, and Einstein.
21%
Flag icon
A man may be attracted to science for all sorts of reasons. Among them are the desire to be useful, the excitement of exploring new territory, the hope of finding order, and the drive to test established knowledge. These motives and others besides also help to determine the particular problems that will later engage him.
51%
Flag icon
during a long course of years, from a point of view directly opposite to mine. . . . [B]ut I look with confidence to the future,—to young and rising naturalists, who will be able to view both sides of the question with impartiality.”7 And Max Planck, surveying his own career in his Scientific Autobiography, sadly remarked that “a new scientific truth does not triumph by convincing its opponents and making them see the light, but rather because its opponents eventually die, and a new generation grows up that is familiar with it.”8
52%
Flag icon
The claim to have solved the crisis-provoking problems is, however, rarely sufficient by itself. Nor can it always legitimately be made.
53%
Flag icon
At most he may wish to say that the man who continues to resist after his whole profession has been converted has ipso facto ceased to be a scientist.
54%
Flag icon
Does a field make progress because it is a science, or is it a science because it makes progress?
55%
Flag icon
Inevitably those remarks will suggest that the member of a mature scientific community is, like the typical character of Orwell’s 1984, the victim of a history rewritten by the powers that be.