The Structure of Scientific Revolutions
Rate it:
Open Preview
Kindle Notes & Highlights
Read between November 21, 2019 - October 9, 2021
4%
Flag icon
exemplar, a very best and most instructive example.
6%
Flag icon
Discovery comes not when something goes right but when something is awry, a novelty that runs counter to what was expected.
6%
Flag icon
We have a tendency to see what we expect, even when it is not there. It often takes a long time for an anomaly to be seen for what it is, something contrary to the established order.
7%
Flag icon
If one theory says the sentence is true and another says it is false, there is no contradiction, for the sentence expresses different statements in the two theories, and they cannot be compared.
10%
Flag icon
“paradigms.” These I take to be universally recognized scientific achievements that for a time provide model problems and solutions to a community of practitioners.
12%
Flag icon
historians confront growing difficulties in distinguishing the “scientific” component of past observation and belief from what their predecessors had readily labeled “error” and “superstition.”
12%
Flag icon
If these out-of-date beliefs are to be called myths, then myths can be produced by the same sorts of methods and held for the same sorts of reasons that now lead to scientific knowledge.
12%
Flag icon
If, on the other hand, they are to be called science, then science has included bodies of belief quite incompatible with the ones we hold today.
13%
Flag icon
The extraordinary episodes in which that shift of professional commitments occurs are the ones known in this essay as scientific revolutions.
13%
Flag icon
the tradition-shattering complements to the tradition-bound activity of normal science.
13%
Flag icon
they can also be retrieved from the study of many other episodes that were not so obviously revolutionary.
14%
Flag icon
there can be a sort of scientific research without paradigms,
15%
Flag icon
In the absence of a paradigm or some candidate for paradigm, all of the facts that could possibly pertain to the development of a given science are likely to seem equally relevant.
15%
Flag icon
early fact-gathering is a far more nearly random activity
17%
Flag icon
a paradigm is rarely an object for replication.
17%
Flag icon
it is an object for further articulation and specification under new or more stringent conditions.
17%
Flag icon
Mopping-up operations are what engage most scientists throughout their careers.
17%
Flag icon
normal science.
17%
Flag icon
No part of the aim of normal science is to call forth new sorts of phenomena;
17%
Flag icon
those that will not fit the box are often not seen at all.
18%
Flag icon
has drastically restricted vision.
18%
Flag icon
those restrictions, born from confidence in a paradigm, turn out to be essential to the development of science.
18%
Flag icon
detail and depth
20%
Flag icon
the range of anticipated, and thus of assimilable, results is always small compared with the range that imagination can conceive.
20%
Flag icon
the project whose outcome does not fall in that narrower range is usually just a research failure, one which reflects not on nature but on the scientist.
20%
Flag icon
Even the project whose goal is paradigm articulation does not aim at the unexpected novelty.
21%
Flag icon
the conviction that, if only he is skilful enough, he will succeed in solving a puzzle that no one before has solved or solved so well.
23%
Flag icon
That scientists do not usually ask or debate what makes a particular problem or solution legitimate tempts us to suppose that, at least intuitively, they know the answer. But it may only indicate that neither the question nor the answer is felt to be relevant to their research.
24%
Flag icon
Normal science can proceed without rules only so long as the relevant scientific community accepts without question the particular problem-solutions already achieved.
25%
Flag icon
Normal science does not aim at novelties of fact or theory and, when successful, finds none.
25%
Flag icon
Discovery commences with the awareness of anomaly, i.e., with the recognition that nature has somehow violated the paradigm-induced expectations that govern normal science. It then continues with a more or less extended exploration of the area of anomaly. And it closes only when the paradigm theory has been adjusted so that the anomalous has become the expected.
27%
Flag icon
consciously or not, the decision to employ a particular piece of apparatus and to use it in a particular way carries an assumption that only certain sorts of circumstances will arise.
27%
Flag icon
Paradigm procedures and applications are as necessary to science as paradigm laws and theories, and they have the same effects. Inevitably they restrict the phenomenological field accessible for scientific investigation at any given time.
27%
Flag icon
theory-induced.
27%
Flag icon
during pre-paradigm periods and during the crises that lead to large-scale changes of paradigm, scientists usually develop many speculative and unarticulated theories that can themselves point the way to discovery. Often, however, that discovery is not quite the one anticipated by the speculative and tentative hypothesis.
27%
Flag icon
Only as experiment and tentative theory are together articulated to a match does the discovery emerge and the theory become a paradigm.
28%
Flag icon
novelty emerges only with difficulty, manifested by resistance, against a background provided by expectation.
28%
Flag icon
Initially, only the anticipated and usual are experienced even under circumstances where anomaly is later to be observed.
28%
Flag icon
Further acquaintance, however, does result in awareness of something wrong or does relate the effect to somet...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
28%
Flag icon
That awareness of anomaly opens a period in which conceptual categories are adjusted until the initially anoma...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
28%
Flag icon
At this point the discovery has be...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
28%
Flag icon
Without the special apparatus that is constructed mainly for anticipated functions, the results that lead ultimately to novelty could not occur.
28%
Flag icon
even when the apparatus exists, novelty ordinarily emerges only for the man who, knowing with precision what he should expect, is able to recognize that something has gone wrong.
28%
Flag icon
Anomaly appears only against the background provided by the paradigm. The more precise and far-reaching that paradigm is, the more sensitive an indicator it provides of anoma...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
28%
Flag icon
resistance guarantees that scientists will not be lightly distracted and that the anomalies that lead to paradigm change will penetrate existing knowledge to the core.
31%
Flag icon
So long as the tools a paradigm supplies continue to prove capable of solving the problems it defines, science moves fastest and penetrates most deeply through confident employment of those tools.
31%
Flag icon
retooling is an extravagance to be reserved for the occasion that demands it.
31%
Flag icon
the act of judgment that leads scientists to reject a previously accepted theory is always based upon more than a comparison of that theory with the world.
31%
Flag icon
The decision to reject one paradigm is always simultaneously the decision to accept another, and the judgment leading to that decision involves the comparison of both paradigms with nature and with each other.
31%
Flag icon
By themselves they cannot and will not falsify that philosophical theory, for its defenders will do what we have already seen scientists doing when confronted by anomaly. They will devise numerous articulations and ad hoc modifications of their theory in order to eliminate any apparent conflict.
« Prev 1 3