Thinking, Fast and Slow
Rate it:
Kindle Notes & Highlights
Read between April 18, 2017 - January 19, 2020
30%
Flag icon
System 1 can deal with stories in which the elements are causally linked, but it is weak in statistical reasoning.
30%
Flag icon
The classic experiment I describe next shows that people will not draw from base-rate information an inference that conflicts with other beliefs. It also supports the uncomfortable conclusion that teaching psychology is mostly a waste of time.
30%
Flag icon
The experiment shows that individuals feel relieved of responsibility when they know that others have heard the same request for help.
30%
Flag icon
Most of us think of ourselves as decent people who would rush to help in such a situation, and we expect other decent people to do the same. The point of the experiment, of course, was to show that this expectation is wrong.
30%
Flag icon
Changing one’s mind about human nature is hard work, and changing one’s mind for the worse about oneself is even harder.
31%
Flag icon
Students who do not develop a new appreciation for the power of social setting have learned nothing of value from the experiment.
31%
Flag icon
In the words of Nisbett and Borgida, students “quietly exempt themselves” (and their friends and acquaintances) from the conclusions of experiments that surprise them.
31%
Flag icon
To teach students any psychology they did not know before, you must surprise them.
31%
Flag icon
Nisbett and Borgida summarize the results in a memorable sentence: Subjects’ unwillingness to deduce the particular from the general was matched only by their willingness to infer the general from the particular.
31%
Flag icon
The test of learning psychology is whether your understanding of situations you encounter has changed, not whether you have learned a new fact.
31%
Flag icon
Statistical results with a causal interpretation have a stronger effect on our thinking than noncausal information. But even compelling causal statistics will not change long-held beliefs or beliefs rooted in personal experience.
31%
Flag icon
You are more likely to learn something by finding surprises in your own behavior than by hearing surprising facts about people in general.
31%
Flag icon
an important principle of skill training: rewards for improved performance work better than punishment of mistakes.
31%
Flag icon
What he had observed is known as regression to the mean, which in that case was due to random fluctuations in the quality of performance.
31%
Flag icon
The instructor had attached a causal interpretation to the inevitable fluctuations of a random process.
31%
Flag icon
I had stumbled onto a significant fact of the human condition: the feedback to which life exposes us is perverse.
32%
Flag icon
regression does not have a causal explanation.
32%
Flag icon
The point to remember is that the change from the first to the second jump does not need a causal explanation. It is a mathematically inevitable consequence of the fact that luck played a role in the outcome of the first jump.
32%
Flag icon
the phenomenon of regression is strange to the human mind. So strange, indeed, that it was first identified and understood two hundred years after the theory of gravitation and differential calculus.
32%
Flag icon
Regression effects can be found wherever we look, but we do not recognize them for what they are.
32%
Flag icon
The correlation coefficient between two measures, which varies between 0 and 1, is a measure of the relative weight of the factors they share.
32%
Flag icon
The correlation between income and education level in the United States is approximately .40.
32%
Flag icon
It took Francis Galton several years to figure out that correlation and regression are not two concepts—they are different perspectives on the same concept. The general rule is straightforward but has surprising consequences: whenever the correlation between two scores is imperfect, there will be regression to the mean.
32%
Flag icon
The observed regression to the mean cannot be more interesting or more explainable than the imperfect correlation.
32%
Flag icon
David Freedman used to say that if the topic of regression comes up in a criminal or civil trial, the side that must explain regression to the jury will lose the case.
32%
Flag icon
our mind is strongly biased toward causal explanations and does not deal well with “mere statistics.”
32%
Flag icon
Our difficulties with the concept of regression originate with both System 1 and System 2. Without special instruction, and in quite a few cases even after some statistical instruction, the relationship between correlation and regression remains obscure. System 2 finds it difficult to understand and learn. This is due in part to the insistent demand for causal interpretations, which is a feature of System 1.
32%
Flag icon
The control group is expected to improve by regression alone, and the aim of the experiment is to determine whether the treated patients improve more than regression can explain.
33%
Flag icon
Regression effects are a common source of trouble in research, and experienced scientists develop a healthy fear of the trap of unwarranted causal inference.
33%
Flag icon
Some intuitions draw primarily on skill and expertise acquired by repeated experience. The rapid and automatic judgments and choices of chess masters, fireground commanders, and physicians that Gary Klein has described in Sources of Power and elsewhere illustrate these skilled intuitions, in which a solution to the current problem comes to mind quickly because familiar cues are recognized.
33%
Flag icon
Other intuitions, which are sometimes subjectively indistinguishable from the first, arise from the operation of heuristics that often substitute an easy question for the harder one that was asked.
33%
Flag icon
Of course, many judgments, especially in the professional domain, are influenced by a combination of analysis and intuition.
33%
Flag icon
We are capable of rejecting information as irrelevant or false, but adjusting for smaller weaknesses in the evidence is not something that System 1 can do.
33%
Flag icon
intuitive predictions are almost completely insensitive to the actual predictive quality of the evidence.
33%
Flag icon
your associative memory quickly and automatically constructs the best possible story from...
This highlight has been truncated due to consecutive passage length restrictions.
33%
Flag icon
People are asked for a prediction but they substitute an evaluation of the evidence, without noticing that the question they answer is not the one they were asked. This process is guaranteed to generate predictions that are systematically biased; they completely ignore regression to the mean.
34%
Flag icon
we have all we need to produce an unbiased prediction. Here are the directions for how to get there in four simple steps: Start with an estimate of average GPA. Determine the GPA that matches your impression of the evidence. Estimate the correlation between your evidence and GPA. If the correlation is .30, move 30% of the distance from the average to the matching GPA.
34%
Flag icon
Step 3 moves you from the baseline toward your intuition, but the distance you are allowed to move depends on your estimate of the correlation.
34%
Flag icon
The approach builds on your intuition, but it moderates it, regresses it toward the mean.
34%
Flag icon
Intuitive predictions need to be corrected because they are not regressive and therefore are biased.
34%
Flag icon
When they are eventually compared to actual outcomes, nonregressive predictions will be found to be biased.
34%
Flag icon
You still make errors when your predictions are unbiased, but the errors are smaller and do not favor either high or low outcomes.
34%
Flag icon
common biases of discrete prediction: neglect of base rates and insensitivity to the quality of information.
34%
Flag icon
Correcting your intuitive predictions is a task for System 2. Significant effort is required to find the relevant reference category, estimate the baseline prediction, and evaluate the quality of the evidence. The effort is justified only when the stakes are high and when you are particularly keen not to make mistakes.
34%
Flag icon
A characteristic of unbiased predictions is that they permit the prediction of rare or extreme events only when the information is very good.
34%
Flag icon
A preference for unbiased predictions is justified if all errors of prediction are treated alike, regardless of their direction. But there are situations in which one type of error is much worse than another.
34%
Flag icon
For a rational person, predictions that are unbiased and moderate should not present a problem.
34%
Flag icon
we are not all rational, and some of us may need the security of distorted estimates to avoid paralysis.
35%
Flag icon
Following our intuitions is more natural, and somehow more pleasant, than acting against them.
35%
Flag icon
We will not learn to understand regression from experience. Even when a regression is identified, as we saw in the story of the flight instructors, it will be given a causal interpretation that is almost always wrong.
1 5 12