Thinking, Fast and Slow
Rate it:
Kindle Notes & Highlights
Read between April 18, 2017 - January 19, 2020
59%
Flag icon
The more vivid description produces a higher decision weight for the same probability.
59%
Flag icon
The power of format creates opportunities for manipulation, which people with an axe to grind know how to exploit.
59%
Flag icon
focal attention and salience contribute to both the overestimation of unlikely events and the overweighting of unlikely outcomes.
59%
Flag icon
Salience is enhanced by mere mention of an event, by its vividness, and by the format in which probability is described.
59%
Flag icon
but underweighting also occurs when people have actually experienced the rare event.
60%
Flag icon
This advice is not impossible to follow. Experienced traders in financial markets live by it every day, shielding themselves from the pain of losses by broad framing.
60%
Flag icon
As expected, broad framing blunted the emotional reaction to losses and increased the willingness to take risks.
60%
Flag icon
The combination of loss aversion and narrow framing is a costly curse.
61%
Flag icon
They would do better by having a risk policy that they routinely apply whenever a relevant problem arises.
61%
Flag icon
A risk policy is a broad frame.
61%
Flag icon
The outside view and the risk policy are remedies against two distinct biases that affect many decisions: the exaggerated optimism of the planning fallacy and the exaggerated caution induced by loss aversion.
61%
Flag icon
There is no guarantee, of course, that the biases cancel out in every situation. An organization that could eliminate both excessive optimism and excessive loss aversion should do so. The combination of the outside view with a risk policy should be the goal.
61%
Flag icon
money is a proxy for points on a scale of self-regard and achievement.
61%
Flag icon
For Humans, mental accounts are a form of narrow framing; they keep things under control and manageable by a finite mind.
61%
Flag icon
As might be expected, finance research has documented a massive preference for selling winners rather than losers—a bias that has been given an opaque label: the disposition effect. The disposition effect is an instance of narrow framing.
61%
Flag icon
The decision to invest additional resources in a losing account, when better investments are available, is known as the sunk-cost fallacy, a costly mistake that is observed in decisions large and small.
62%
Flag icon
In the presence of sunk costs, the manager’s incentives are misaligned with the objectives of the firm and its shareholders, a familiar type of what is known as the agency problem.
62%
Flag icon
Regret is one of the counterfactual emotions that are triggered by the availability of alternatives to reality.
62%
Flag icon
This short example illustrates a broad story: people expect to have stronger emotional reactions (including regret) to an outcome that is produced by action than to the same outcome when it is produced by inaction.
62%
Flag icon
The asymmetry is at least as strong for losses, and it applies to blame as well as to regret.
62%
Flag icon
Losses are weighted about twice as much as gains in several contexts: choice between gambles, the endowment effect, and reactions to price changes.
63%
Flag icon
The taboo tradeoff against accepting any increase in risk is not an efficient way to use the safety budget.
63%
Flag icon
The intense aversion to trading increased risk for some other advantage plays out on a grand scale in the laws and regulations governing risk. This trend is especially strong in Europe, where the precautionary principle, which prohibits any action that might cause harm, is a widely accepted doctrine.
63%
Flag icon
As the jurist Cass Sunstein points out, the precautionary principle is costly, and when interpreted strictly it can be paralyzing.
63%
Flag icon
But enhanced loss aversion is embedded in a strong and widely shared moral intuition; it originates in System 1. The dilemma between intensely loss-averse moral attitudes and efficient risk management does not have a simple and compelling solution.
63%
Flag icon
You can also take precautions that will inoculate you against regret. Perhaps the most useful is to be explicit about the anticipation of regret. If you can remember when things go badly that you considered the possibility of regret carefully before deciding, you are likely to experience less of it.
63%
Flag icon
You should also know that regret and hindsight bias will come together, so anything you can do to preclude hindsight is likely to be helpful.
63%
Flag icon
Poignancy (a close cousin of regret) is a counterfactual feeling, which is evoked because the thought “if only he had shopped at his regular store…” comes readily to mind.
63%
Flag icon
The emotional reactions of System 1 are much more likely to determine single evaluation; the comparison that occurs in joint evaluation always involves a more careful and effortful assessment, which calls for System 2.
64%
Flag icon
You should not form the impression that single and joint evaluations are always inconsistent, or that judgments are completely chaotic. Our world is broken into categories for which we have norms, such as six-year-old boys or tables.
64%
Flag icon
The result illustrates Hsee’s evaluability hypothesis: The number of entries is given no weight in single evaluation, because the numbers are not “evaluable” on their own. In joint evaluation, in contrast, it is immediately obvious that dictionary B is superior on this attribute, and it is also apparent that the number of entries is far more important than the condition of the cover.
64%
Flag icon
There is good reason to believe that the administration of justice is infected by predictable incoherence in several domains.
65%
Flag icon
As we have seen, rationality is generally served by broader and more comprehensive frames, and joint evaluation is obviously broader than single evaluation.
65%
Flag icon
For the purpose of logical reasoning, the two descriptions of the outcome of the match are interchangeable because they designate the same state of the world. As philosophers say, their truth conditions are identical: if one of these sentences is true, then the other is true as well.
65%
Flag icon
The two sentences evoke markedly different associations. “Italy won” evokes thoughts of the Italian team and what it did to win. “France lost” evokes thoughts of the French team and what it did that caused it to lose,
65%
Flag icon
Someone whose preferences are reality-bound would give the same answer to both questions, but such individuals are rare. In fact, one version attracts many more positive answers: the second.
65%
Flag icon
We should not be surprised: losses evokes stronger negative feelings than costs. Choices are not reality-bound because System 1 is not reality-bound.
65%
Flag icon
The two may be economically equivalent, but they are not emotionally equivalent.
65%
Flag icon
The authors ranked the 20 subjects accordingly and gave the ranking a striking label: the rationality index.
65%
Flag icon
The amygdala is accessed very rapidly by emotional stimuli—and it is a likely suspect for involvement in System 1.
65%
Flag icon
region known to be associated with conflict and self-control (the anterior cingulate) was more active when subjects did not do what comes naturally—
65%
Flag icon
The most “rational” subjects—those who were the least susceptible to framing effects—showed enhanced activity in a frontal area of the brain that is implicated in combining emotion and reasoning to guide decisions.
65%
Flag icon
It appears that these elite participants were (often, not always) reality-bound with little conflict.
66%
Flag icon
An important finding of the study is that physicians were just as susceptible to the framing effect as medically unsophisticated people (hospital patients and graduate students in a business school). Medical training is, evidently, no defense against the power of framing.
66%
Flag icon
Reframing is effortful and System 2 is normally lazy. Unless there is an obvious reason to do otherwise, most of us passively accept decision problems as they are framed and therefore rarely have an opportunity to discover the extent to which our preferences are frame-bound rather than reality-bound.
66%
Flag icon
but we must get used to the idea that even important decisions are influenced, if not governed, by System 1.
66%
Flag icon
Most people find that their System 2 has no moral intuitions of its own to answer the question.
66%
Flag icon
The surprising aspect of Schelling’s problem is that this apparently simple moral rule does not work reliably. It generates contradictory answers to the same problem, depending on how that problem is framed.
66%
Flag icon
Our preferences are about framed problems, and our moral intuitions are about descriptions, not about substance.
67%
Flag icon
As we have seen again and again, an important choice is controlled by an utterly inconsequential feature of the situation. This is embarrassing—it is not how we would wish to make important decisions. Furthermore, it is not how we experience the workings of our mind, but the evidence for these cognitive illusions is undeniable.