What do you think?
Rate this book
236 pages, Paperback
First published January 1, 1989
”If the inner truth of gender is a fabrication and if a true gender is a fantasy instituted and inscribed on the surface of bodies, then it seems that genders can neither be true or false, but are only produced as the truth effects of a discourse of a primary and stable identity.”
"The 'unthinkable' is thus fully within culture, but fully excluded from dominant culture. The theory which presumes bisexuality or homosexuality as the 'before' to culture and then locates that 'priority' as the source of a prediscursive subversion, effectively forbids from within the terms of the culture the very subversion that it ambivalently defends and defends against... in the case of Kristeva, subversion thus becomes a futile gesture, entertained only in a derealized aesthetic mode which can never be translated into other cultural practices."
"[The] structure of religious tragedy in Lacanian theory effectively undermines any strategy of cultural politics to configure an alternative imaginary for the play of desires. If the Symbolic guarantees the failure of the tasks it commands, perhaps its purposes, like those of the Old Testament God, are altogether unteleological—not the accomplishment of some goal, but obedience and suffering to enforce the 'subject’s' sense of limitation 'before the law.' There is, of course, the comic side to this drama that is revealed through the disclosure of the permanent impossibility of the realization of identity. But even this comedy is the inverse expression of an enslavement to the God that it claims to be unable to overcome. Lacanian theory must be understood as a kind of 'slave morality.' How would Lacanian theory be reformulated after the appropriation of Nietzsche’s insight in On the Genealogy of Morals that God, the inaccessible Symbolic, is rendered inaccessible by a power (the will-to-power) that regularly institutes its own powerlessness? This figuration of the paternal law as the inevitable and unknowable authority before which the sexed subject is bound to fail must be read for the theological impulse that motivates it as well as for the critique of theology that points beyond it. The construction of the law that guarantees failure is symptomatic of a slave morality that disavows the very generative powers it uses to construct the 'Law' as a permanent impossibility. What is the power that creates this fiction that reflects inevitable subjection? What are the cultural stakes in keeping power within that self-negating circle, and how might that power be reclaimed from the trappings of a prohibitive law that is that power in its dissimulation and self-subjection?"
‘Gender is the repeated stylisation of the body, a set of repeated acts within a highly rigid regulatory frame that congeal over time to produce the appearance of substance, of a natural sort of being’
Originally intended to dispute the biology-is-destiny formulation, the distinction between sex and gender serves the argument that whatever biological intractability sex appears to have, gender is culturally constructed: hence, gender is neither the causal result of sex nor as seemingly fixed as sex. (6)Thence: “If the immutable character of sex is contested, perhaps this construct called ‘sex’ is as culturally constructed as gender; indeed, perhaps it was always already gender, with the consequence that the distinction between sex and gender turns out to be no distinction at all” (7)—which is not a rigorous argument for the implosion of the binary, but rather a hypothetical, a thought experiment, upon which the remainder of the argument proceeds. I propose to make true the thought experiment herein.
There is nothing in her account that guarantees that the ‘one’ who becomes a woman is necessarily female. If ‘the body is a situation,’ as she claims, there is no recourse to a body that has not always already been interpreted by cultural meanings; hence, sex could not qualify as a prediscursive anatomical facticity. Indeed, sex, by definition, will have been shown to have been gender all along. (8)This is, again, not rigorous argumentation for the implosion, but rather an immanent critique of basic feminist theory on the principle of sex/gender differentiation—what we might designate as primary differentiation, as opposed to secondary differentiation radiating thereunder, between the feminine/masculine (purported indicia of ‘gender’), on the one hand, and the female/male (alleged indicia of ‘sex’ so-called), on the other.
‘Intelligible’ genders are those which in some sense institute and maintain relations of coherence and continuity among sex, gender, sexual practice, and desire. In other words, the spectres of discontinuity and incoherence, themselves thinkable only in relation to existing norms of continuity and coherence, are constantly prohibited and produced by the very laws that seek to establish causal or expressive lines of connection among biological sex, culturally constituted gender, and the ‘expression’ or ‘effect’ of both in the manifestation of sexual desire through sexual practice. (17)I’d go however a step further by including coherence/continuity in the indicia of so-called biological sex—internal genitalia, external genitalia, gametes, hormones, chromosomes—all of which take on their purported binary character solely through reference to the gender ideology that they are alleged otherwise to constitute. That is, there is nothing inherent to these anatomical markers to render them male or female individually, and we have instances of their not ‘matching up,’ as detailed in the long head-scratching over so-called ‘hermaphroditism,’ what we might designate now more sagely as intersex, the existence of which should trouble not only primary differentiation, but should rather solicit the secondary differentiation of binary sex, male/female. Butler does not get into these debates very much (though we can always reference Fine’s Delusions of Gender and Fausto-Sterling’s Sexing the Body for some of the raw data).
essay remains committed to a distinction between sex and gender which assumes the discrete and prior ontological reality of a ‘sex’ which is done over in the name of the law, that is, transformed subsequently into ‘gender.’ This narrative of gender acquisition requires a certain temporal ordering of events which assumes that the narrator is in some position to ‘know’ both what is before and after the law. And yet the narration takes places within a language which, strictly speaking, is after the law, the consequence of the law. (74)All good times. Similarly, “insofar as Kristeva conceptualizes this maternal instinct as having an ontological status prior to the paternal law, she fails to consider the way in which that very law might well be the cause of the very desire it is said to repress” (90).
The task of distinguishing sex from gender becomes all the more difficult once we understand that gendered meanings frame the hypothesis and the reasoning of those biomedical inquiries that seek to establish ‘sex’ for us as it is prior to those cultural meanings that it acquires. Indeed, the task is even more complicated when we realize that the language of biology participates in other kinds of languages and reproduces that cultural sedimentation in the objects it purports to discover and neutrally describe. (109)In her analysis of Wittig, author notes quite irresistibly that “‘sex’ imposes an artificial unity on an otherwise discontinuous set of attributes” (114), a “historically contingent epistemic regime” (id.). That last is salient, and suggests the appropriate frame of analysis: Althusser’s theory of the ideological state apparatus--
What are ideological state apparatuses (ISAs)? They must not be confused with the (repressive) state apparatus. Remember that in Marxist theory, the state apparatus contains: the government, the administration, the army, the police, the courts, the prisons, etc., which constitute what I shall in the future call the repressive state apparatuses. Repressive suggests that the state apparatus in question ‘functions by violence’ – at least ultimately […] I shall call ideological state apparatuses a certain number of realities which present themselves to the immediate observer in the form of distinct and specialized institutions. I propose an empirical list of these which will obviously have to be examined in detail. (Lenin & Philosophy, “Ideology & Ideological State Apparatuses at 142-43)He then lists out various institutions, such as the religious ISA, the educational, the family, the legal, and so on. These institutions “function massively and predominantly by ideology, but they also function secondarily by repression, even if ultimately, but only ultimately, this is very attenuated and concealed, even symbolic” (loc. cit. at 145). The School and the Church accordingly “use suitable methods of punishment, expulsion, selection, etc., to ‘discipline’ not only their shepherds, but also their flocks” (id.). The “ideology by which they function is always in fact united, despite its diversity and contradictions, beneath the ruling ideology, which is the ideology of the ‘ruling class’” (loc. cit. at 146). These institutions “may not only be the stake, but also the site of class struggle” (147). The ruling class “cannot lay down the law in the ISAs as easily as it can in the [RSA], not only because the former ruling classes are able to retain strong positions there for a long time, but also because the resistance of the exploited classes is able to find means and occasions to express itself” (id.). The ultimate aim of ideology: “Ideology represents the imaginary relationship of individuals [sic] to their real conditions of existence” (162). Ideology functions by means of both illusion of the Imaginary but also allusion to the Real (id.). That is, “What is represented in ideology is therefore not the system of real relations which govern the existence of individuals [sic], but the imaginary relation of those individuals to the real relations in which they live” (165).